Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 1/2018

Open Access 01-03-2018 | Original Research

Engendering Harm: A Critique of Sex Selection For “Family Balancing”

Author: Arianne Shahvisi

Published in: Journal of Bioethical Inquiry | Issue 1/2018

Login to get access

Abstract

The most benign rationale for sex selection is deemed to be “family balancing.” On this view, provided the sex distribution of an existing offspring group is “unbalanced,” one may legitimately use reproductive technologies to select the sex of the next child. I present four novel concerns with granting “family balancing” as a justification for sex selection: (a) families or family subsets should not be subject to medicalization; (b) sex selection for “family balancing” entrenches heteronormativity, inflicting harm in at least three specific ways; (c) the logic of affirmative action is appropriated; (d) the moral mandate of reproductive autonomy is misused. I conclude that the harms caused by family balancing are sufficiently substantive to override any claim arising from a supposed right to sex selection as an instantiation of procreative autonomy.
Footnotes
1
There is a notable exception to this trend. In the United States, most of those using Microsort sperm sorting request a female embryo. However, the reason for this is likely to be linked to the fact that Microsort promises higher success rates for female embryos: a 91 per cent success rate, compared with a 76 per cent success rate for males (Grady 2007). A 2011 survey by U.S.-based research consultancy Gallup Inc. found that if only permitted to have one child, 40 per cent of participants would prefer a son and 28 per cent a daughter (Newport 2011).
 
2
Consider that sons will have higher lifetime earnings, have access to a wider range of professional opportunities, will not incur dowry payments (where relevant), will in most cases keep the family name, are unlikely to be subject to sexual and/or domestic violence, etc.
 
3
The requirements have since changed and, reassuringly, no longer require the couple to be married, but I include McMillan’s endorsement since he presumably agreed with this additional requirement, given that the requirement still applied at the time of the paper’s publication. I do so in order to demonstrate a prejudice towards heteronormativity within the provision of reproductive technologies themselves, and amongst many interlocutors who uncritically endorse them.
 
4
In institutional settings, chromosomal sex may play a role, but that is a very different discussion, which I take up in section 5.
 
5
I say “in the first instance” because some of the most influential and robust gendering of small children will be enacted by influences outside the home and will likely happen in spite of parents’ aspirations towards gender-neutral parenting. That is “prospective sex selectors must make their decisions in the real social world, an environment that may well be sexist and which will almost certainly impact on future children’s characters whether the parents like it or not” (Wilkinson 2008, 387). One then might argue the following: I don’t intend to gender my children, but I know that they will likely nonetheless end up gendered in accordance with how their sexed-bodies are construed. I do not want a child who might be violent, thoughtless, and irresponsible, as young men are often socialized to be, and I do not feel that my parenting can offset this powerful norm. I am therefore selecting a female child. This is an important argument, but note that it does nothing to undermine arguments against sex selection for family balancing specifically, since parents who want variably gendered children are likely to encourage gendered properties alongside, and in accordance with, external influences.
 
6
Sparrow (2013) carefully considers the ethics of the inverse situation: that of selecting against intersex chromosomes, carefully weighing the virtue of challenging the sex binary by resisting the reduction of the intersex population against the cost of personal suffering (to parents and children) due to the marginalization of non-normative genitals. He makes the important point that the “political project of combating such injustices, seems to demand that parents sacrifice the interests of their children for the sake of the larger social good” (34). I find this point compelling and uncomfortable (as does he) but do not have space to explore it further here.
 
Literature
go back to reference Aghajanova, L., and C.T. Valdes. 2012. Sex selection for nonhealth related reasons. Virtual Mentor 14(2): 105.CrossRefPubMed Aghajanova, L., and C.T. Valdes. 2012. Sex selection for nonhealth related reasons. Virtual Mentor 14(2): 105.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Bandyopadhyay, M. 2014. Sex selection: Issues and concerns. The Wiley Blackwell encyclopedia of health, illness, behavior, and society. Bandyopadhyay, M. 2014. Sex selection: Issues and concerns. The Wiley Blackwell encyclopedia of health, illness, behavior, and society.
go back to reference Barr, R., and H. Hayne. 2003. It’s not what you know, it's who you know: Older siblings facilitate imitation during infancy. International Journal of Early Years Education 11(1): 7–21. Barr, R., and H. Hayne. 2003. It’s not what you know, it's who you know: Older siblings facilitate imitation during infancy. International Journal of Early Years Education 11(1): 7–21.
go back to reference Bhatia, R., 2010. Constructing gender from the inside out: Sex-selection practices in the United States. Feminist Studies 36(2): 260–291. Bhatia, R., 2010. Constructing gender from the inside out: Sex-selection practices in the United States. Feminist Studies 36(2): 260–291.
go back to reference Browne, T.K. 2017a. Why parents should not be told the sex of their fetus. Journal of Medical Ethics 43(1): 5–10.CrossRefPubMed Browne, T.K. 2017a. Why parents should not be told the sex of their fetus. Journal of Medical Ethics 43(1): 5–10.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference ____. 2017b. How sex selection undermines reproductive autonomy. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 14(2): 195–204. ____. 2017b. How sex selection undermines reproductive autonomy. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 14(2): 195–204.
go back to reference Butler, J. 1990. Gender trouble: Feminism and the subversion of identity. New York: Routledge. Butler, J. 1990. Gender trouble: Feminism and the subversion of identity. New York: Routledge.
go back to reference Caplan, P.J., and J. Caplan. 2015. Thinking critically about research on sex and gender. Oxon and New York: Psychology Press. Caplan, P.J., and J. Caplan. 2015. Thinking critically about research on sex and gender. Oxon and New York: Psychology Press.
go back to reference Costa, P.A., and M. Davies. 2012. Portuguese adolescents’ attitudes toward sexual minorities: Transphobia, homophobia, and gender role beliefs. Journal of Homosexuality 59(10): 1424–1442.CrossRefPubMed Costa, P.A., and M. Davies. 2012. Portuguese adolescents’ attitudes toward sexual minorities: Transphobia, homophobia, and gender role beliefs. Journal of Homosexuality 59(10): 1424–1442.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Dahl, E. 2005. Sex selection: Laissez faire or family balancing? Health Care Analysis 13(1): 87–90.CrossRefPubMed Dahl, E. 2005. Sex selection: Laissez faire or family balancing? Health Care Analysis 13(1): 87–90.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference ____. 2004. The presumption in favour of liberty: A comment on the HFEA’s public consultation on sex selection. Reproductive Biomedicine Online 8(3): 266–267. ____. 2004. The presumption in favour of liberty: A comment on the HFEA’s public consultation on sex selection. Reproductive Biomedicine Online 8(3): 266–267.
go back to reference Dahl, E., K.D. Hinsch, M. Beutel, and B. Brosig. 2003. Preconception sex selection for non-medical reasons: A representative survey from the UK. Human Reproduction 18(10): 2238–2239.CrossRefPubMed Dahl, E., K.D. Hinsch, M. Beutel, and B. Brosig. 2003. Preconception sex selection for non-medical reasons: A representative survey from the UK. Human Reproduction 18(10): 2238–2239.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Davis, D.S. 2009. The parental investment factor and the child’s right to an open future. Hastings Center Report 39(2): 24–27.CrossRefPubMed Davis, D.S. 2009. The parental investment factor and the child’s right to an open future. Hastings Center Report 39(2): 24–27.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Davis, D.S. 1997. Genetic dilemmas and the child’s right to an open future. Hastings Center Report 27(2):7–15.CrossRefPubMed Davis, D.S. 1997. Genetic dilemmas and the child’s right to an open future. Hastings Center Report 27(2):7–15.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference de Melo-Martín, I. 2013. Sex selection and the procreative liberty framework. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 23(1): 1–18.CrossRefPubMed de Melo-Martín, I. 2013. Sex selection and the procreative liberty framework. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 23(1): 1–18.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Fausto-Sterling, A. 2008. Myths of gender: Biological theories about women and men. New York: Basic Books. Fausto-Sterling, A. 2008. Myths of gender: Biological theories about women and men. New York: Basic Books.
go back to reference ____. 2000. Sexing the body: Gender politics and the construction of sexuality. New York: Basic Books. ____. 2000. Sexing the body: Gender politics and the construction of sexuality. New York: Basic Books.
go back to reference Goldberg, A.E. 2009. Heterosexual, lesbian, and gay preadoptive parents’ preferences about child gender. Sex Roles 61(1–2): 55–71.CrossRef Goldberg, A.E. 2009. Heterosexual, lesbian, and gay preadoptive parents’ preferences about child gender. Sex Roles 61(1–2): 55–71.CrossRef
go back to reference Goodkind, D. 1999. Should prenatal sex selection be restricted? Ethical questions and their implications for research and policy. Population Studies 53(1): 49–61.CrossRef Goodkind, D. 1999. Should prenatal sex selection be restricted? Ethical questions and their implications for research and policy. Population Studies 53(1): 49–61.CrossRef
go back to reference Grant, V.J. 2006. Sex predetermination and the ethics of sex selection. Human Reproduction 21(7): 1659–1661.CrossRefPubMed Grant, V.J. 2006. Sex predetermination and the ethics of sex selection. Human Reproduction 21(7): 1659–1661.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Haslanger, S. 2012 What are we talking about? The semantics and politics of social kinds. In Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique, edited by S. Haslanger, 365–380. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Haslanger, S. 2012 What are we talking about? The semantics and politics of social kinds. In Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique, edited by S. Haslanger, 365–380. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Heng, B.C. 2006. Regulated family balancing by equalizing the sex-ratio of gender-selected births. Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics 23(7): 319–320.CrossRefPubMed Heng, B.C. 2006. Regulated family balancing by equalizing the sex-ratio of gender-selected births. Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics 23(7): 319–320.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Hesketh, T., and Z.W. Xing. 2006. Abnormal sex ratios in human populations: Causes and consequences. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 103(36): 13271–13275.CrossRef Hesketh, T., and Z.W. Xing. 2006. Abnormal sex ratios in human populations: Causes and consequences. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 103(36): 13271–13275.CrossRef
go back to reference Hill, K., and D.M. Upchurch. 1995. Gender differences in child health: Evidence from the demographic and health surveys. Population and Development Review 21: 127–151.CrossRef Hill, K., and D.M. Upchurch. 1995. Gender differences in child health: Evidence from the demographic and health surveys. Population and Development Review 21: 127–151.CrossRef
go back to reference Holm, S. 2004. Like a frog in boiling water: The public, the HFEA and sex selection. Health Care Analysis 12(1): 27–39.CrossRefPubMed Holm, S. 2004. Like a frog in boiling water: The public, the HFEA and sex selection. Health Care Analysis 12(1): 27–39.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Illich, I. 1976. Limits to medicine. Marion Boyars. Illich, I. 1976. Limits to medicine. Marion Boyars.
go back to reference Kane, E.W. 2009. “I wanted a soul mate”: Gendered anticipation and frameworks of accountability in parents’ preferences for sons and daughters. Symbolic Interaction 32(4): 372–389.CrossRef Kane, E.W. 2009. “I wanted a soul mate”: Gendered anticipation and frameworks of accountability in parents’ preferences for sons and daughters. Symbolic Interaction 32(4): 372–389.CrossRef
go back to reference Leiter, G. 2014. What Israeli policy can teach us about elective sex selection. Israel Journal of Health Policy Research 3(1): 1.CrossRef Leiter, G. 2014. What Israeli policy can teach us about elective sex selection. Israel Journal of Health Policy Research 3(1): 1.CrossRef
go back to reference Lowe, P. 2015. Milk for a girl and bananas for a boy: Recipes and reasons for sex-preference practices in a British Internet forum. Women’s Reproductive Health 2(2): 111–123.CrossRef Lowe, P. 2015. Milk for a girl and bananas for a boy: Recipes and reasons for sex-preference practices in a British Internet forum. Women’s Reproductive Health 2(2): 111–123.CrossRef
go back to reference McGowan, M.L., and R.R. Sharp. 2013. Justice in the context of family balancing. Science, Technology, & Human Values 38(2): 271–293.CrossRef McGowan, M.L., and R.R. Sharp. 2013. Justice in the context of family balancing. Science, Technology, & Human Values 38(2): 271–293.CrossRef
go back to reference Minnett, A.M., D. L. Vandell, and J.W. Santrock. 1983. The effects of sibling status on sibling interaction: Influence of birth order, age spacing, sex of child, and sex of sibling. Child Development 54(4): 1064–1072.CrossRef Minnett, A.M., D. L. Vandell, and J.W. Santrock. 1983. The effects of sibling status on sibling interaction: Influence of birth order, age spacing, sex of child, and sex of sibling. Child Development 54(4): 1064–1072.CrossRef
go back to reference Moazam, F. 2004. Feminist discourse on sex screening and selective abortion of female foetuses. Bioethics 18(3): 205–220.CrossRefPubMed Moazam, F. 2004. Feminist discourse on sex screening and selective abortion of female foetuses. Bioethics 18(3): 205–220.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Mohapatra, S. 2015. False framings: The co-opting of sex-selection by the anti-abortion movement. The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 43(2): 270–274.CrossRef Mohapatra, S. 2015. False framings: The co-opting of sex-selection by the anti-abortion movement. The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 43(2): 270–274.CrossRef
go back to reference Mudde, A. 2010. “Before you formed in the womb I knew you”: Sex selection and spaces of ambiguity. Hypatia 25(3): 553–576.CrossRef Mudde, A. 2010. “Before you formed in the womb I knew you”: Sex selection and spaces of ambiguity. Hypatia 25(3): 553–576.CrossRef
go back to reference Norton, A.T., and G.M. Herek. 2013. Heterosexuals’ attitudes toward transgender people: Findings from a national probability sample of U.S. adults. Sex Roles 68(11–12): 738–753.CrossRef Norton, A.T., and G.M. Herek. 2013. Heterosexuals’ attitudes toward transgender people: Findings from a national probability sample of U.S. adults. Sex Roles 68(11–12): 738–753.CrossRef
go back to reference Nugent, C.N. 2013. Wanting mixed-sex children: Separate spheres, rational choice, and symbolic capital motivations. Journal of Marriage and Family 75(4): 886–902.CrossRef Nugent, C.N. 2013. Wanting mixed-sex children: Separate spheres, rational choice, and symbolic capital motivations. Journal of Marriage and Family 75(4): 886–902.CrossRef
go back to reference Pebley, A.F., and C.P. Westoff. 1982. Women’s sex preferences in the United States 1970–1975. Demography 19: 177–189.CrossRefPubMed Pebley, A.F., and C.P. Westoff. 1982. Women’s sex preferences in the United States 1970–1975. Demography 19: 177–189.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Pennings, G. 1996. Ethics of sex selection for family balancing: Family balancing as a morally acceptable application of sex selection. Human Reproduction 11(11): 2339–2345.CrossRefPubMed Pennings, G. 1996. Ethics of sex selection for family balancing: Family balancing as a morally acceptable application of sex selection. Human Reproduction 11(11): 2339–2345.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Pepler, D.J., R. Abramovitch, and C. Corter. 1981. Sibling interaction in the home: A longitudinal study. Child Development 52(4):1344–1347.CrossRef Pepler, D.J., R. Abramovitch, and C. Corter. 1981. Sibling interaction in the home: A longitudinal study. Child Development 52(4):1344–1347.CrossRef
go back to reference Riggs, D.W., K. Webber, and G.R. Fell. 2012. Australian undergraduate psychology students’ attitudes towards trans people. Gay and Lesbian Issues and Psychology Review 8(1): 52. Riggs, D.W., K. Webber, and G.R. Fell. 2012. Australian undergraduate psychology students’ attitudes towards trans people. Gay and Lesbian Issues and Psychology Review 8(1): 52.
go back to reference Robertson, J. A. 2004. Gender variety as a valid choice: A comment on the HFEA–response to Edgar Dahl’s “The presumption in favour of liberty.” Reproductive Biomedicine Online 8(3): 270–271.CrossRefPubMed Robertson, J. A. 2004. Gender variety as a valid choice: A comment on the HFEA–response to Edgar Dahl’s “The presumption in favour of liberty.” Reproductive Biomedicine Online 8(3): 270–271.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference ____. 2001. Preconception gender selection. American Journal of Bioethics 1(1): 2–9. ____. 2001. Preconception gender selection. American Journal of Bioethics 1(1): 2–9.
go back to reference Rose, S.M. 1985. Same-and cross-sex friendships and the psychology of homosociality. Sex Roles 12(1–2): 63–74.CrossRef Rose, S.M. 1985. Same-and cross-sex friendships and the psychology of homosociality. Sex Roles 12(1–2): 63–74.CrossRef
go back to reference Sandel, M.J. 2009. The case against perfection. Harvard University Press. Sandel, M.J. 2009. The case against perfection. Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Savulescu, J. 1999. Sex selection: The case for. Medical Journal of Australia 171: 373–375.PubMed Savulescu, J. 1999. Sex selection: The case for. Medical Journal of Australia 171: 373–375.PubMed
go back to reference Seavilleklein, V., and S. Sherwin. 2007. The myth of the gendered chromosome: Sex selection and the social interest. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 16(1): 7–19.CrossRefPubMed Seavilleklein, V., and S. Sherwin. 2007. The myth of the gendered chromosome: Sex selection and the social interest. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 16(1): 7–19.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Sharp, R.R., M.L McGowan, J.A Verma, et al. 2010. Moral attitudes and beliefs among couples pursuing PGD for sex selection. Reproductive Biomedicine Online 21(7): 838–847.CrossRefPubMed Sharp, R.R., M.L McGowan, J.A Verma, et al. 2010. Moral attitudes and beliefs among couples pursuing PGD for sex selection. Reproductive Biomedicine Online 21(7): 838–847.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Sparrow, R., 2013. Gender eugenics? The ethics of PGD for intersex conditions. The American Journal of Bioethics 13(10): 29–38.CrossRefPubMed Sparrow, R., 2013. Gender eugenics? The ethics of PGD for intersex conditions. The American Journal of Bioethics 13(10): 29–38.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Steinbacher, R., and R. Ericsson. 1994. Should parents be prohibited from choosing the sex of their child? Health 8(2): 24.PubMed Steinbacher, R., and R. Ericsson. 1994. Should parents be prohibited from choosing the sex of their child? Health 8(2): 24.PubMed
go back to reference Strange, H., and R. Chadwick. 2009. The ethics of nonmedical sex selection. Health Care Analysis 18(3): 252–266.CrossRef Strange, H., and R. Chadwick. 2009. The ethics of nonmedical sex selection. Health Care Analysis 18(3): 252–266.CrossRef
go back to reference Wilkinson, S. 2008. Sexism, sex selection, and “family balancing.” Medical Law Review 16(3): 369–389.CrossRefPubMed Wilkinson, S. 2008. Sexism, sex selection, and “family balancing.” Medical Law Review 16(3): 369–389.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Van Balen, F., and M.C. Inhorn. 2003. Son preference, sex selection, and the “new” new reproductive technologies. International Journal of Health Services 33(2): 235–252.CrossRefPubMed Van Balen, F., and M.C. Inhorn. 2003. Son preference, sex selection, and the “new” new reproductive technologies. International Journal of Health Services 33(2): 235–252.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Vidal, C. 2012. The sexed brain: Between science and ideology. Neuroethics 5(3): 295–303.CrossRef Vidal, C. 2012. The sexed brain: Between science and ideology. Neuroethics 5(3): 295–303.CrossRef
go back to reference ____. 2005. Brain, sex and ideology. Diogenes 52(4): 127–133. ____. 2005. Brain, sex and ideology. Diogenes 52(4): 127–133.
Metadata
Title
Engendering Harm: A Critique of Sex Selection For “Family Balancing”
Author
Arianne Shahvisi
Publication date
01-03-2018
Publisher
Springer Singapore
Published in
Journal of Bioethical Inquiry / Issue 1/2018
Print ISSN: 1176-7529
Electronic ISSN: 1872-4353
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-017-9835-4

Other articles of this Issue 1/2018

Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 1/2018 Go to the issue