Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2/2019

01-06-2019 | Scientific Contribution

Rethinking the doctor–patient relationship: toward a hermeneutically-informed epistemology of medical practice

Author: Paul Healy

Published in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy | Issue 2/2019

Login to get access

Abstract

Although typically implicit, clinicians face an inherent conflict between their roles as medical healers and as providers of technical biomedicine (Scott et al. in Philos Ethics Humanit Med 4:11, 2009). This conflict arises from the tension between the physicalist model which still predominates in medical training and practice and the extra-physicalist dimensions of medical practice as epitomised in the concept of patient-centred care. More specifically, the problem is that, as grounded in a “borrowed” physicalist philosophy, the dominant “applied scientist” model exhibits a number of limitations which severely restrict its ability to underwrite the effective practice of care. Moreover, being structural in character, these problems cannot be resolved by piecemeal modifications of the existing model, nor by an appeal to evidence-based medicine (Miles in J Eval Clin Pract 15(6):887–890, 2009; Miles in Folia Med 55(1):5–24, 2013; Miles et al. in J Eval Clin Pract 14(5):621–649, 2008). Hence, the need for medical theorists to “partner with experts in the humanities to build a sui generis philosophy of medicine” (Whatley in J Eval Clin Pract 20(6):961–964, 2014, p. 961). In response, the present paper seeks to vindicate the merits of hermeneutically-informed template in providing the requisite grounding. While capable of correcting for the limitations of the applied scientist model, a hermeneutically-informed template is a “both/and” approach, which seeks to complement rather than exclude the physicalist dimension, and thereby aspires to reconcile technical mastery with patient-centred care, rather than eschew one in favour of the other. As such, it can provide a cogent philosophical template for current best practice, which does justice to the art as well as the science of medical care.
Footnotes
1
Thus, as Tymieniecka and Agazzi put it, the aim is to foster “a more mature consciousness” oriented toward the development of “a medicine better in keeping with its task of taking care of the patients in the global perception of their needs” (2001, p. xiii).
 
2
While Polkinghorne’s area of specialisation is psychological counselling, his book addresses philosophical issues pertaining to the practice of care more generally, including medical practice.
 
3
In delineating a hermeneutic template appropriate for the medical context, I draw on the work of Hans-Georg Gadamer, with particular reference to concepts developed in his major work, Truth and Method (Gadamer 1989). In so doing, I go beyond Gadamer himself in seeking to crystallise their application to patient-centred care. Moreover, like other hermeneutically-informed commentators (e.g., Árnason 2000; Landes 2015; Svenaeus 2003; Widdershoven 2000), I find the themes developed in Gadamer’s major work (such as I–Thou relations, phronesis, and dialogue) more directly relevant in this connection than the ideas proffered in his later collection of essays entitled The Enigma of Health (Gadamer 1996).
 
4
As Svenaeus puts it: “The clinical encounter can be viewed as a coming-together of the two different attitudes and lifeworlds of doctor and patient—in the language of Gadamer, of their different horizons of understanding—aimed at establishing a mutual understanding, which can benefit the health of the ill party” (2003, p. 416).
 
5
This could be further explicated in terms of the “transformative” use of power and knowledge whereby, as elaborated by Wartenberg (1990, chap. 10), the imbalance is used productively to enhance the well-being of the relatively disempowered participant (here, the patient).
 
6
Hence, although from a positivistic EBM perspective uncertainty is typically regarded as an untenable limitation, with Popper, a hermeneutic approach endorses uncertainty as an ineliminable hallmark of scientific inquiry, and embraces its potential to stimulate an investigative, discovery-oriented form of inquiry (cf. Buetow 2001; Sturmberg and Martin 2008).
 
7
Ruitenberg epitomises what is at issue as follows:
“… the technically skilful application of scientific and technological resources alone does not make one a doctor; for that, one also needs to be able to reach a thoughtful professional judgement about what the patient needs are that this skilful application purportedly serves, and whether the various needs of the patient—as there is never just one—are relatively better served with this, or another, or perhaps a combination of skilful applications of scientific and technological resources. …the acquisition of scientific knowledge and training in technical skills are necessary but not sufficient for the preparation of doctors” (2013, p. 957).
 
Literature
go back to reference Árnason, Vilhjalmur. 2000. Gadamerian dialogue in the patient-professional interaction. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy: A European Journal 3 (1): 17–23.CrossRef Árnason, Vilhjalmur. 2000. Gadamerian dialogue in the patient-professional interaction. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy: A European Journal 3 (1): 17–23.CrossRef
go back to reference Árnason, Vilhjalmur, and Stefan Hjorleifsson. 2016. The person in a state of sickness: The doctor-patient relationship reconsidered. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25 (2): 209–218.CrossRef Árnason, Vilhjalmur, and Stefan Hjorleifsson. 2016. The person in a state of sickness: The doctor-patient relationship reconsidered. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25 (2): 209–218.CrossRef
go back to reference Brown, Harold I. 1990. Rationality. London: Routledge. Brown, Harold I. 1990. Rationality. London: Routledge.
go back to reference Buetow, Stephen. 2011. The virtue of uncertainty in health care. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17 (5): 873–876.CrossRef Buetow, Stephen. 2011. The virtue of uncertainty in health care. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17 (5): 873–876.CrossRef
go back to reference Chessick, Richard D. 1995. The application of phenomenology to psychiatry and psychotherapy. American Journal of Psychotherapy 49 (2): 159–162.CrossRef Chessick, Richard D. 1995. The application of phenomenology to psychiatry and psychotherapy. American Journal of Psychotherapy 49 (2): 159–162.CrossRef
go back to reference Crawford, James M. 2007. Original research in pathology: Judgment, or evidence-based medicine? Laboratory Investigation 87 (2): 104–114.CrossRef Crawford, James M. 2007. Original research in pathology: Judgment, or evidence-based medicine? Laboratory Investigation 87 (2): 104–114.CrossRef
go back to reference Flyvbjerg, Bent. 2001. Making social science matter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Flyvbjerg, Bent. 2001. Making social science matter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 1989. Truth and method (trans: Joel Weinsheimer, and Donald Marshall). 2nd Aufl. New York: Continuum. Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 1989. Truth and method (trans: Joel Weinsheimer, and Donald Marshall). 2nd Aufl. New York: Continuum.
go back to reference Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 1996. The enigma of health: The art of healing in a scientific age. Cambridge: Polity Press. Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 1996. The enigma of health: The art of healing in a scientific age. Cambridge: Polity Press.
go back to reference Ladrière, Jean. 2001. Is it possible to give sense to illness? In Life: Interpretation and the sense of illness within the human condition: Medicine and philosophy in a dialogue (Analecta Husserliana volume 72), ed. Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka and Evandro Agazzi, 153–179. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.CrossRef Ladrière, Jean. 2001. Is it possible to give sense to illness? In Life: Interpretation and the sense of illness within the human condition: Medicine and philosophy in a dialogue (Analecta Husserliana volume 72), ed. Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka and Evandro Agazzi, 153–179. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.CrossRef
go back to reference Landes, Donald A. 2015. Phronēsis and the art of healing: Gadamer, Merleau-Ponty, and the phenomenology of equilibrium in health. Human Studies 38 (2): 261–279.CrossRef Landes, Donald A. 2015. Phronēsis and the art of healing: Gadamer, Merleau-Ponty, and the phenomenology of equilibrium in health. Human Studies 38 (2): 261–279.CrossRef
go back to reference Loughlin, Michael. 2008. Reason, reality and objectivity—Shared dogmas and distortions in the way both ‘scientistic’ and ‘postmodern’ commentators frame the EBM debate. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 14 (5): 665–671.CrossRef Loughlin, Michael. 2008. Reason, reality and objectivity—Shared dogmas and distortions in the way both ‘scientistic’ and ‘postmodern’ commentators frame the EBM debate. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 14 (5): 665–671.CrossRef
go back to reference Miles, Andrew. 2009. Towards a medicine of the whole person–knowledge, practice and holism in the care of the sick. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 15 (6): 887–890.CrossRef Miles, Andrew. 2009. Towards a medicine of the whole person–knowledge, practice and holism in the care of the sick. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 15 (6): 887–890.CrossRef
go back to reference Miles, Andrew. 2013. Science, humanism, judgement, ethics: Person-centered medicine as an emergent model of modern clinical practice. Folia Medica 55 (1): 5–24.CrossRef Miles, Andrew. 2013. Science, humanism, judgement, ethics: Person-centered medicine as an emergent model of modern clinical practice. Folia Medica 55 (1): 5–24.CrossRef
go back to reference Miles, Andrew, Michael Loughlin, and Andreas Polychronis. 2008. Evidence-based healthcare, clinical knowledge and the rise of personalised medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 14 (5): 621–649.CrossRef Miles, Andrew, Michael Loughlin, and Andreas Polychronis. 2008. Evidence-based healthcare, clinical knowledge and the rise of personalised medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 14 (5): 621–649.CrossRef
go back to reference Mitchell, Derek. 2011. Four alternatives to a reductive view of knowledge (seeing with a squint. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17 (5): 899–904.CrossRef Mitchell, Derek. 2011. Four alternatives to a reductive view of knowledge (seeing with a squint. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17 (5): 899–904.CrossRef
go back to reference Phillips, James. 1996. Key concepts: Hermeneutics. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (1): 61–69.CrossRef Phillips, James. 1996. Key concepts: Hermeneutics. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (1): 61–69.CrossRef
go back to reference Polkinghorne, Donald E. 2004. Practice and the human sciences: The case for a judgement-based practice of care. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press. Polkinghorne, Donald E. 2004. Practice and the human sciences: The case for a judgement-based practice of care. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
go back to reference Ruitenberg, Claudia. 2013. Why the conception of the doctor as applied scientist is inadequate. Medical Education 47 (10): 956–957.CrossRef Ruitenberg, Claudia. 2013. Why the conception of the doctor as applied scientist is inadequate. Medical Education 47 (10): 956–957.CrossRef
go back to reference Scott, John G., Rebecca G. Scott, William L. Miller, Kurt C. Stange, and Benjamin F. Crabtree. 2009. Healing relationships and the existential philosophy of Martin Buber. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 4: 11.CrossRef Scott, John G., Rebecca G. Scott, William L. Miller, Kurt C. Stange, and Benjamin F. Crabtree. 2009. Healing relationships and the existential philosophy of Martin Buber. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 4: 11.CrossRef
go back to reference Sturmberg, Joachim P., and Carmel M. Martin. 2008. Knowing-in medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 14 (5): 767–770.CrossRef Sturmberg, Joachim P., and Carmel M. Martin. 2008. Knowing-in medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 14 (5): 767–770.CrossRef
go back to reference Svenaeus, Fredrik. 2003. Hermeneutics of medicine in the wake of Gadamer: The issue of Phronesis. Philosophy of Medical Research and Practice 24 (5): 407–431. Svenaeus, Fredrik. 2003. Hermeneutics of medicine in the wake of Gadamer: The issue of Phronesis. Philosophy of Medical Research and Practice 24 (5): 407–431.
go back to reference Tymieniecka, Anna-Teresa, and Evandro Agazzi. 2001. Editors’ introduction: The complex phenomenon of illness. In Life: Interpretation and the sense of illness within the human condition: Medicine and philosophy in a dialogue (Analecta Husserliana volume 72), ed. Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka and Evandro Agazzi, xi–xiii. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.CrossRef Tymieniecka, Anna-Teresa, and Evandro Agazzi. 2001. Editors’ introduction: The complex phenomenon of illness. In Life: Interpretation and the sense of illness within the human condition: Medicine and philosophy in a dialogue (Analecta Husserliana volume 72), ed. Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka and Evandro Agazzi, xi–xiii. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.CrossRef
go back to reference Wartenberg, Thomas. 1990. The forms of power: From domination to transformation. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Wartenberg, Thomas. 1990. The forms of power: From domination to transformation. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
go back to reference Whatley, Shawn D. 2014. Borrowed philosophy: Bedside physicalism and the need for a sui generis metaphysic of medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 20 (6): 961–964.CrossRef Whatley, Shawn D. 2014. Borrowed philosophy: Bedside physicalism and the need for a sui generis metaphysic of medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 20 (6): 961–964.CrossRef
go back to reference Widdershoven, Guy A. 2000. The doctor-patient relationship as a Gadamerian dialogue: A response to Arnason. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy: A European Journal 3 (1): 25–27.CrossRef Widdershoven, Guy A. 2000. The doctor-patient relationship as a Gadamerian dialogue: A response to Arnason. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy: A European Journal 3 (1): 25–27.CrossRef
go back to reference Williams, Richard N. 1990. The metaphysic of things and discourse about them. In Reconsidering psychology, ed. James E. Faulconer and Richard N. Williams, 136–150. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press. Williams, Richard N. 1990. The metaphysic of things and discourse about them. In Reconsidering psychology, ed. James E. Faulconer and Richard N. Williams, 136–150. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
Metadata
Title
Rethinking the doctor–patient relationship: toward a hermeneutically-informed epistemology of medical practice
Author
Paul Healy
Publication date
01-06-2019
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy / Issue 2/2019
Print ISSN: 1386-7423
Electronic ISSN: 1572-8633
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-018-9875-5

Other articles of this Issue 2/2019

Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2/2019 Go to the issue