Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Health Care Analysis 2/2019

Open Access 01-06-2019 | Original Article

Principles of Need and the Aggregation Thesis

Authors: Erik Gustavsson, Niklas Juth

Published in: Health Care Analysis | Issue 2/2019

Login to get access

Abstract

Principles of need are constantly referred to in health care priority setting. The common denominator for any principle of need is that it will ascribe some kind of special normative weight to people being worse off. However, this common ground does not answer the question how a plausible principle of need should relate to the aggregation of benefits across individuals. Principles of need are sometimes stated as being incompatible with aggregation and sometimes characterized as accepting aggregation in much the same way as utilitarians do. In this paper we argue that if one wants to take principles of need seriously both of these positions have unreasonable implications. We then characterize and defend a principle of need consisting of sufficientarian elements as well as prioritarian which avoids these unreasonable implications.
Footnotes
1
Hence, when we refer to cost-effectiveness in this paper we do not refer to cost-effective analysis, which is an analytic tool for providing so-called cost-effectiveness ratios, rather than a principle for resource allocation.
 
2
For a discussion about the conceptual structure of needs see e.g. [12, 13, 27, 41, 44, 45].
 
3
In contrast to intrapersonal aggregation, which is concerned with how different parts of an individual’s life are combined. Moreover, we are interested in same number cases in this text. The issue of possible people may raise very different puzzles.
 
4
To combine a principle of need with a conception of health that entails an optimal level implies that if there are improvements that can be made for people above the optimal level, these people cannot have need-based claims to such improvements. This may, for example, rule out entitlements to some forms of enhancements. For the idea of optimal health in the holistic theory see further Nordenfelt [30, esp. pp. 97–98].
 
5
To have 0 represent death may be controversial. We make this assumption for simplicity reasons. It seems that there may be states that are worse than death. For a discussion on so-called negative QALYs see e.g. [36].
 
6
This kind of example may also be used in order to bring out the intuition (which we shall not discuss here) that small benefits to a large number of people should not outweigh large benefits to a few. Such an implication may be referred to as “welfare diffusion” [cf. 33].
 
7
Assume also that these patients are alike in all other relevant respects.
 
8
However, not necessarily all sorts of aggregation. For instance, one may accept principles that allow for interpersonal comparison but not continuity that would bar utilitarian principles but allow solutions to the different-number cases in favour of saving the many over the few; that would mean allowing aggregation but not unrestricted aggregation [see 19, esp. 19–41; 147–154]. We do not deny this; in fact our own solution favours aggregation but bars unrestricted aggregation. Moreover, writers like Kamm and Scanlon have claimed that they can provide an approach that justifies saving the many over the few without appealing to aggregation. This is often referred to as the Kamm–Scanlon argument. Space permits us from fully discuss this view here. It is contested, however, whether they in fact are appealing to aggregation [cf. 17].
 
9
For a recent discussion on the priority view see the special issue in Utilitas, 24, 3 (2012). To understand the priority view in this way is to exclude Absolute Priority discussed and rejected by [5, 8].
 
10
This point is also made by Crisp [8, p. 754].
 
11
For discussions about the arbitrariness of positioning the threshold see [1, 3, 4, 20, esp. pp. 127–134].
 
12
The focus on treatments also allow us to exclude research and development of new treatments from the following discussion.
 
13
Employment of multi-level versions of sufficiency principles has been done by others [see e.g. 3, 4, 23]. The thresholds in DTP are, however, specifically employed in order to handle questions about aggregation.
 
14
This will be assumed from now on.
 
15
Following Crisp here, we assume that these benefits are non-trivial.
 
16
In Official Norwegian Reports [31] it is also differentiated between three groups of severity. The purpose of these groups is different however. While we provide a deontic constrain of how tradeoffs are allowed between groups the Norwegian report suggests that we should allow for different cost per QALY (quality adjusted life years) within each group.
 
17
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing us to discuss this kind of case.
 
18
Consider also Crisp’s theory outlined above. Crisp uses mild hay fever as an example of a condition above the threshold and severe schizophrenia as an example of a condition below it.
 
19
Obviously, there is much more to be said about the issue of transitivity but a full discussion of this notion is far beyond the scope of this paper [see e.g. 39, see also 42].
 
20
Voorhoeve [43] also discusses this series of choices. However, our aim here is not to discuss Voorhoeve’s answer to this objection but to show that DTP can handle these kinds of worries.
 
Literature
1.
go back to reference Arneson, R. (2000). Luck-egalitarianism and prioritarianism. Ethics, 110, 338–445.CrossRef Arneson, R. (2000). Luck-egalitarianism and prioritarianism. Ethics, 110, 338–445.CrossRef
3.
go back to reference Benbaji, Y. (2005). The doctrine of sufficiency: A defence. Utilitas, 17, 310–332.CrossRef Benbaji, Y. (2005). The doctrine of sufficiency: A defence. Utilitas, 17, 310–332.CrossRef
4.
go back to reference Benbaji, Y. (2006). Sufficiency or priority? European Journal of Philosophy, 14, 327–348.CrossRef Benbaji, Y. (2006). Sufficiency or priority? European Journal of Philosophy, 14, 327–348.CrossRef
6.
7.
go back to reference Crisp, R. (2002). Treatment according to need: Justice and the British national health service. In R. Rhodes (Ed.), Medicine and social justice: Essays on the distribution of health care (pp. 134–143). New York: Oxford University Press. Crisp, R. (2002). Treatment according to need: Justice and the British national health service. In R. Rhodes (Ed.), Medicine and social justice: Essays on the distribution of health care (pp. 134–143). New York: Oxford University Press.
8.
go back to reference Crisp, R. (2003). Equality, priority, and compassion. Ethics, 113, 745–763.CrossRef Crisp, R. (2003). Equality, priority, and compassion. Ethics, 113, 745–763.CrossRef
9.
go back to reference Fleurbaey, M., Tungodden, B., & Vallentyne, P. (2009). On the possibility of nonaggregative priority to the worst off. Social Philosophy and Policy, 26, 258–285.CrossRef Fleurbaey, M., Tungodden, B., & Vallentyne, P. (2009). On the possibility of nonaggregative priority to the worst off. Social Philosophy and Policy, 26, 258–285.CrossRef
10.
go back to reference Frankfurt, H. G. (1984). Necessity and desire. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 45, 1–13.CrossRef Frankfurt, H. G. (1984). Necessity and desire. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 45, 1–13.CrossRef
11.
12.
13.
go back to reference Gustavsson, E., & Sandman, L. (2015). Health care needs and shared decision making in priority setting. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 18, 13–22.CrossRef Gustavsson, E., & Sandman, L. (2015). Health care needs and shared decision making in priority setting. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 18, 13–22.CrossRef
14.
go back to reference Halliday, D. (2011). Endowments, inequality, and aggregation: An inquiry into the foundations and methods of distributive justice. Dissertation, Stanford University, 2011. Halliday, D. (2011). Endowments, inequality, and aggregation: An inquiry into the foundations and methods of distributive justice. Dissertation, Stanford University, 2011.
15.
go back to reference Hasman, A., Hope, T., & Østerdal, L. P. (2006). Health care need: Three interpretations. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 23, 145–156.CrossRefPubMed Hasman, A., Hope, T., & Østerdal, L. P. (2006). Health care need: Three interpretations. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 23, 145–156.CrossRefPubMed
16.
go back to reference Herlitz, A., & Horan, D. (2016). Measuring needs for priority setting in healthcare planning and policy. Social Science & Medicine, 157, 96–102.CrossRef Herlitz, A., & Horan, D. (2016). Measuring needs for priority setting in healthcare planning and policy. Social Science & Medicine, 157, 96–102.CrossRef
17.
go back to reference Hirose, I. (2007). Aggregation and non-utilitarian moral theories. The Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4, 273–284.CrossRef Hirose, I. (2007). Aggregation and non-utilitarian moral theories. The Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4, 273–284.CrossRef
18.
go back to reference Hirose, I. (2013). Aggregation and the separateness of persons. Utilitas, 25, 182–205.CrossRef Hirose, I. (2013). Aggregation and the separateness of persons. Utilitas, 25, 182–205.CrossRef
19.
go back to reference Hirose, I. (2015). Moral aggregation. New York: Oxford University Press. Hirose, I. (2015). Moral aggregation. New York: Oxford University Press.
20.
go back to reference Hirose, I. (2015). Egalitarianism. New York: Routledge. Hirose, I. (2015). Egalitarianism. New York: Routledge.
21.
go back to reference Hoffman, B. (2013). Priority setting in health care: Trends and models from Scandinavian experiences. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 16, 349–356.CrossRef Hoffman, B. (2013). Priority setting in health care: Trends and models from Scandinavian experiences. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 16, 349–356.CrossRef
22.
go back to reference Hope, T., Østerdal, L. P., & Hasman, A. (2010). An inquiry into the principles of needs-based allocation of health care. Bioethics, 24, 470–480.CrossRefPubMed Hope, T., Østerdal, L. P., & Hasman, A. (2010). An inquiry into the principles of needs-based allocation of health care. Bioethics, 24, 470–480.CrossRefPubMed
23.
go back to reference Huseby, R. (2010). Sufficiency: Restated and defended. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 18, 178–197.CrossRef Huseby, R. (2010). Sufficiency: Restated and defended. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 18, 178–197.CrossRef
25.
go back to reference Juth, N. (2015). Challenges for principles of need in health care. Health Care Analysis, 23, 73–87.CrossRefPubMed Juth, N. (2015). Challenges for principles of need in health care. Health Care Analysis, 23, 73–87.CrossRefPubMed
26.
go back to reference Lindsay, M. S., & Reidar, L. K. (2008). Priority setting in health care: Lessons from the experiences of eight countries. International Journal for Equity in Health. doi:10.1186/1475-9276-7-4.CrossRef Lindsay, M. S., & Reidar, L. K. (2008). Priority setting in health care: Lessons from the experiences of eight countries. International Journal for Equity in Health. doi:10.​1186/​1475-9276-7-4.CrossRef
27.
go back to reference Liss, P.-E. (1993). Health care need—Meaning and measurement. Aldershot: Avebury. Liss, P.-E. (1993). Health care need—Meaning and measurement. Aldershot: Avebury.
28.
go back to reference Ministry of Health and Social Affairs. (1995). Swedish Government Official Reports (SOU 1995:5). Priorities in health care—ethics, economy, implementation. Final report from the Swedish parliamentary priorities commission. Fritzes: Stockholm. Ministry of Health and Social Affairs. (1995). Swedish Government Official Reports (SOU 1995:5). Priorities in health careethics, economy, implementation. Final report from the Swedish parliamentary priorities commission. Fritzes: Stockholm.
29.
go back to reference Nord, E. (1993). The trade-off between severity of illness and treatment effect in cost-value analysis of health care. Health Policy, 24, 227–238.CrossRefPubMed Nord, E. (1993). The trade-off between severity of illness and treatment effect in cost-value analysis of health care. Health Policy, 24, 227–238.CrossRefPubMed
30.
go back to reference Nordenfelt, L. (1995). On the nature of health: An action-theoretic approach. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRef Nordenfelt, L. (1995). On the nature of health: An action-theoretic approach. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRef
31.
go back to reference Official Norwegian Reports. (2014: 12). Open and fair—priority setting in the health service (Åpent og rettferdig—prioriteringer i helsetjenesten). Oslo: Departementenes sikkerhets- og serviceorganisasjon. Official Norwegian Reports. (2014: 12). Open and fairpriority setting in the health service (Åpent og rettferdigprioriteringer i helsetjenesten). Oslo: Departementenes sikkerhets- og serviceorganisasjon.
32.
33.
go back to reference Persson, I. (2011). Prioritarianism, levelling down and welfare diffusion. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 14, 307–311.CrossRef Persson, I. (2011). Prioritarianism, levelling down and welfare diffusion. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 14, 307–311.CrossRef
34.
go back to reference Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
36.
go back to reference Robinson, A., & Spencer, A. (2006). Exploring challenges to TTO utilities: Valuing states worse than death. Health Economics, 15, 393–402.CrossRefPubMed Robinson, A., & Spencer, A. (2006). Exploring challenges to TTO utilities: Valuing states worse than death. Health Economics, 15, 393–402.CrossRefPubMed
37.
go back to reference Swedish Health Care Act. (1982: 763), 2 §. Swedish Health Care Act. (1982: 763), 2 §.
38.
go back to reference Taurek, J. (1977). Should the numbers count? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 6, 293–316. Taurek, J. (1977). Should the numbers count? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 6, 293–316.
39.
go back to reference Temkin, L. (2001). Worries about continuity, transitivity, expected utility theory, and practical reasoning. In D. Egonsson, J. Josefsson, B. Petersson, & T. Rønnow-Rasmussen (Eds.), Exploring practical philosophy (pp. 95–108). Farnham: Ashgate Publishing Limited. Temkin, L. (2001). Worries about continuity, transitivity, expected utility theory, and practical reasoning. In D. Egonsson, J. Josefsson, B. Petersson, & T. Rønnow-Rasmussen (Eds.), Exploring practical philosophy (pp. 95–108). Farnham: Ashgate Publishing Limited.
41.
go back to reference Thomson, G. (1987). Needs. New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Thomson, G. (1987). Needs. New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
42.
go back to reference Voorhoeve, A. (2013). Vaulting intuition: Temkin’s critique of transitivity. Economics & Philosophy, 29, 409–423.CrossRef Voorhoeve, A. (2013). Vaulting intuition: Temkin’s critique of transitivity. Economics & Philosophy, 29, 409–423.CrossRef
43.
go back to reference Voorhoeve, A. (2014). How should we aggregate competing claims? Ethics, 125, 64–87.CrossRef Voorhoeve, A. (2014). How should we aggregate competing claims? Ethics, 125, 64–87.CrossRef
44.
go back to reference Wiggins, D. (1998). Needs, values, truth (3rd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Wiggins, D. (1998). Needs, values, truth (3rd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
45.
go back to reference Wiggins, D. (2005). An idea we cannot do without. In S. Reader (Ed.), The philosophy of need (pp. 25–50). Cambridge: Cambridge University. Wiggins, D. (2005). An idea we cannot do without. In S. Reader (Ed.), The philosophy of need (pp. 25–50). Cambridge: Cambridge University.
Metadata
Title
Principles of Need and the Aggregation Thesis
Authors
Erik Gustavsson
Niklas Juth
Publication date
01-06-2019
Publisher
Springer US
Published in
Health Care Analysis / Issue 2/2019
Print ISSN: 1065-3058
Electronic ISSN: 1573-3394
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-017-0346-6

Other articles of this Issue 2/2019

Health Care Analysis 2/2019 Go to the issue