Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2/2013

01-05-2013 | Review Article

Merleau-Ponty’s sexual schema and the sexual component of body integrity identity disorder

Author: Helena De Preester

Published in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy | Issue 2/2013

Login to get access

Abstract

Body integrity identity disorder (BIID), formerly also known as apotemnophilia, is characterized by a desire for amputation of a healthy limb and is claimed to straddle or to even blur the boundary between psychiatry and neurology. The neurological line of approach, however, is a recent one, and is accompanied or preceded by psychodynamical, behavioural, philosophical, and psychiatric approaches and hypotheses. Next to its confusing history in which the disorder itself has no fixed identity and could not be classified under a specific discipline, its sexual component has been an issue of unclarity and controversy, and its assessment a criterion for distinguishing BIID from apotemnophilia, a paraphilia. Scholars referring to the lived body—a phenomenon primarily discussed in the phenomenological tradition in philosophy—seem willing to exclude the sexual component as inessential, whereas other authors notice important similarities with gender identity disorder or transsexualism, and thus precisely focus attention on the sexual component. This contribution outlines the history of BIID highlighting the vicissitudes of its sexual component, and questions the justification for distinguishing BIID from apotemnophilia and thus for omitting the sexual component as essential. Second, we explain a hardly discussed concept from Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Perception (1945a), the sexual schema, and investigate how the sexual schema could function in interaction with the body image in an interpretation of BIID which starts from the lived body while giving the sexual component its due.
Footnotes
1
A distinction is made on the basis of a traditional paraphilia classification in pairs, in which one term is reciprocal to the other (e.g. sadism and masochism). In this case, the pair consists of autoapotemnophilia (self-directed) and alloapotemnophilia (other-directed) (cf. Money et al. 1977, p. 124).
 
2
In the same year, a second publication by Wakefield et al. (1977) appears that describes another case.
 
3
In 1977, apotemnophilia and acrotomophilia were not clearly distinguished by Money. Both fell under the name of apotemnophilia, although the latter had two faces: self-directed or other-directed (see also note 1).
 
4
Earlier surveys exist. The earliest survey was made in 1976, by Ampix, a company selling stories and photographs of amputees. A second one was made in 1996 (see Lawrence 2006 for details). These surveys, however, recruited acrotomophiles rather than apotemnophiles, although in the second survey, of 50 devotees, 22% agreed that they would like to be an amputee (cf. Lawrence 2006, p. 264).
 
5
For an account of how experiences of in- and overcompleteness may issue from the normative dimension of an unusal body-model, (cf. De Preester et al. 2009).
 
6
The percentages in First (2004) Table 1 p. 922: ‘Reasons provided (in open-ended narrative) for wanting amputation’ and in Table 3, p. 924: ‘Co-occurence of restoring identity and sexual arousal as motivations for desire for amputation’ differ with n = 1 for ‘Restoring true identity as an amputee’ (with −1 for primary reason and +1 for secondary reason), but this does not considerably influence the percentages. Based on the percentages of Table 6 (this article), the two percentages together even are as high as 77%.
 
7
Earlier, in 2000, Frith and colleague (Furth et al. 2000) proposed the name Amputee Identity Disorder (see Lawrence 2006) but the name did not catch on.
 
8
Body image is distinct from body schema. For a clarification, cf. note 11.
 
9
Homosexual male-to-female transsexualism includes persons who were overtly feminine as children and very feminine as adults and who are exclusively attracted to men. Non-homosexual male-to-female transsexualism includes persons who do not show these characteristics, and who may be sexually attracted to women, to women and men, or to neither sex (cf. Lawrence 2006 p. 265).
 
10
According to Kant, in the Critique of Pure Reason ([1781/1787] 1998), experience and knowledge are a result of subsuming the givens of intuition under the categories of the understanding. Without intuition, the understanding remains empty, but without the concepts of the understanding, intuition remains blind. Sexual and erotic perception is, according to Merleau-Ponty, blind in the latter sense. This blindness implies that sexual and erotic preferences cannot be objectified.
 
11
Merleau-Ponty tries to elucidate the operation of the sexual schema by comparing it to the body schema. It is important to notice that body image and body schema differ in important respects. “The conceptual distinction between body image and body schema is related to the difference between having a perception of (or belief about) something and having a capacity to move (or an ability to do something). We can characterize the body image as involving perceptions, mental representations, beliefs, and attitudes where the intentional object of such perceptions, beliefs, etc. (that which they are directed towards or that which they are about) is one’s own body. The body schema, in contrast, involves certain motor capacities, abilities, and habits that enable movement and the maintenance of posture. It continues to operate, and in many cases operates best, when the intentional object of perception is something other than one’s own body.” (Gallagher and Meltzoff 1996, p. 215).
The English version of Phénoménologie de la Perception translates ‘schéma corporel’ as ‘body image’, whereas the characteristics of the sexual schema resemble better those of the body schema than those of the body image. Moreover, and in spite of the Merleau-Ponty’s lack of differentiation between body image and body schema, Merleau-Ponty explicitly refers to the context of movement and thus to the body schema when discussing the sexual schema (cf. Phénoménologie de la Perception, Paris: Gallimard, 1945a, p. 196).
 
Literature
go back to reference Bayne, T., and N. Levy. 2005. Amputees by choice: Body integrity identity disorder and the ethics of amputation. Journal of Applied Philosophy 22(1): 75–86.CrossRefPubMed Bayne, T., and N. Levy. 2005. Amputees by choice: Body integrity identity disorder and the ethics of amputation. Journal of Applied Philosophy 22(1): 75–86.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Becerra, R. 2004. “Atmosphere”, a precursor of “cognitive schemas”: Tracing tacit phenomenological influences on cognitive behaviour therapy. Indo-Pacific Journal of Phenomenology 4(1): 1–13. Becerra, R. 2004. “Atmosphere”, a precursor of “cognitive schemas”: Tracing tacit phenomenological influences on cognitive behaviour therapy. Indo-Pacific Journal of Phenomenology 4(1): 1–13.
go back to reference Bensler, J.M., and D.S. Paauw. 2003. Apotemnophilia masquerading as medical morbidity. Cse report. Southern Medical Association 96(7): 674–676.CrossRef Bensler, J.M., and D.S. Paauw. 2003. Apotemnophilia masquerading as medical morbidity. Cse report. Southern Medical Association 96(7): 674–676.CrossRef
go back to reference Blanke, O., F.D. Morgenthaler, P. Brugger, and L.S. Overney. 2009. Preliminary evidence for a fronto-parietal dysfunction in able-bodied participant with a desired for limb amputation. Journal of Neuropsychology 3: 181–200.CrossRefPubMed Blanke, O., F.D. Morgenthaler, P. Brugger, and L.S. Overney. 2009. Preliminary evidence for a fronto-parietal dysfunction in able-bodied participant with a desired for limb amputation. Journal of Neuropsychology 3: 181–200.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Brang, D., P.D. McGeoch, and V.S. Ramachandran. 2008. Apotemnophilia: A neurological disorder. Neuroreport: Cognitive Neuroscience and Neuropsychology 19(13): 1305–1306. Brang, D., P.D. McGeoch, and V.S. Ramachandran. 2008. Apotemnophilia: A neurological disorder. Neuroreport: Cognitive Neuroscience and Neuropsychology 19(13): 1305–1306.
go back to reference De Preester, H., and M. Tsakiris. 2009. Body-extension versus body- incorporation: Is there a need for a body-model? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8(3): 307–319.CrossRef De Preester, H., and M. Tsakiris. 2009. Body-extension versus body- incorporation: Is there a need for a body-model? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8(3): 307–319.CrossRef
go back to reference Donix, M., and T. Reuster. 2007. ‘Apotemnophilie. Zur diagnostischen Klassifikation zwischen Paraphilie und Körper-Integritäts-Identitätsstörung’. Nervenheilkund 6: 477–479. Donix, M., and T. Reuster. 2007. ‘Apotemnophilie. Zur diagnostischen Klassifikation zwischen Paraphilie und Körper-Integritäts-Identitätsstörung’. Nervenheilkund 6: 477–479.
go back to reference Everaerd, W. 1983. A case of ampotemnophilia: A handicap as sexual preference. American Journal of Psychotherapy 37(2): 285–293.PubMed Everaerd, W. 1983. A case of ampotemnophilia: A handicap as sexual preference. American Journal of Psychotherapy 37(2): 285–293.PubMed
go back to reference First, M.B. 2004. Desire for amputation of a limb: Paraphilia, psychosis, or a new type of identity disorder. Psychological Medicine 35: 919–928.CrossRef First, M.B. 2004. Desire for amputation of a limb: Paraphilia, psychosis, or a new type of identity disorder. Psychological Medicine 35: 919–928.CrossRef
go back to reference Freund, K., and R. Blanchard. 1993. Erotic target location error in male gender dysphorics, paedophiles, and fetishists. British Journal of Psychiatry 162: 558–563.CrossRefPubMed Freund, K., and R. Blanchard. 1993. Erotic target location error in male gender dysphorics, paedophiles, and fetishists. British Journal of Psychiatry 162: 558–563.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Furth, G.M., and R. Smith. 2000. Amputee identity disorder: Information, questions, answers, and recommendations about self-demand amputation. Bloomington, IN: 1st Books. Furth, G.M., and R. Smith. 2000. Amputee identity disorder: Information, questions, answers, and recommendations about self-demand amputation. Bloomington, IN: 1st Books.
go back to reference Gallagher, S., and J. Cole. 1995. Body schema and body image in a differenced subject. Journal of Mind and Behaviour 16: 369–390. Gallagher, S., and J. Cole. 1995. Body schema and body image in a differenced subject. Journal of Mind and Behaviour 16: 369–390.
go back to reference Gallagher, S., and A.N. Meltzoff. 1996. The earliest sense of self and others: Merleau-Ponty and recent developmental studies. Philosophical Psychology 9(2): 211–233.CrossRef Gallagher, S., and A.N. Meltzoff. 1996. The earliest sense of self and others: Merleau-Ponty and recent developmental studies. Philosophical Psychology 9(2): 211–233.CrossRef
go back to reference Hilti, L.M., and P. Brugger. 2010. Incarnation and animation: Physical versus representational deficits of body integrity. Experimental Brain Research 204: 315–326.CrossRef Hilti, L.M., and P. Brugger. 2010. Incarnation and animation: Physical versus representational deficits of body integrity. Experimental Brain Research 204: 315–326.CrossRef
go back to reference Johnston, J., and C. Elliott. 2002. Healthy limb amputation: Ethical and legal aspects. Clinical Medicine 2(5): 431–435.CrossRefPubMed Johnston, J., and C. Elliott. 2002. Healthy limb amputation: Ethical and legal aspects. Clinical Medicine 2(5): 431–435.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Kant, Immanuel. [1781/1787] 1998. Critique of Pure Reason (The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant in Translation). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kant, Immanuel. [1781/1787] 1998. Critique of Pure Reason (The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant in Translation). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Kasten, E. 2009. Body integrity identity disorder (BIID): Befragung von Betroffenen und Erklärungsansätze. Fortschritte der Neurologie Psychiatrie 77(1): 16–24.CrossRefPubMed Kasten, E. 2009. Body integrity identity disorder (BIID): Befragung von Betroffenen und Erklärungsansätze. Fortschritte der Neurologie Psychiatrie 77(1): 16–24.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Lawrence, A.A. 2006. Clinical and theoretical parallels between desire for limb amputation and gender identity disorder. Archives of Sexual Behavior 35(3): 263–278.CrossRefPubMed Lawrence, A.A. 2006. Clinical and theoretical parallels between desire for limb amputation and gender identity disorder. Archives of Sexual Behavior 35(3): 263–278.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Lowenstein, L.F. 2002. Fetishes and their associated behavior. Sexuality and Disability 20(2): 135–147.CrossRef Lowenstein, L.F. 2002. Fetishes and their associated behavior. Sexuality and Disability 20(2): 135–147.CrossRef
go back to reference McGeoch, P.D., Brang, D.J., and Ramachandran, V.S. 2009. A new right parietal syndrome? In Body integrity disorder: psychological, neurobiological, ethical and legal aspects, eds. Stirn, A., Thiel, A., Oddo, S, 225–237. Lengerich: PABST Science Publishers. McGeoch, P.D., Brang, D.J., and Ramachandran, V.S. 2009. A new right parietal syndrome? In Body integrity disorder: psychological, neurobiological, ethical and legal aspects, eds. Stirn, A., Thiel, A., Oddo, S, 225–237. Lengerich: PABST Science Publishers.
go back to reference Merleau-Ponty, M. 1945a. Phénoménologie de la Perception. Paris: Gallimard. Merleau-Ponty, M. 1945a. Phénoménologie de la Perception. Paris: Gallimard.
go back to reference Merleau-Ponty, M. [1945b] 2002. Phenomenology of perception (Trans: Smith, C). London/New York: Routledge. Merleau-Ponty, M. [1945b] 2002. Phenomenology of perception (Trans: Smith, C). London/New York: Routledge.
go back to reference Money, J., R. Jobaris, and G. Furth. 1977. Apotemnophilia: Two cases of self-demand amputation as a paraphilia. The Journal of Sex Research 13(2): 115–125.CrossRef Money, J., R. Jobaris, and G. Furth. 1977. Apotemnophilia: Two cases of self-demand amputation as a paraphilia. The Journal of Sex Research 13(2): 115–125.CrossRef
go back to reference Money, J. 1984. Paraphilias–phenomenology and classification. American Journal of Psychotherapy 38(2): 164–179.PubMed Money, J. 1984. Paraphilias–phenomenology and classification. American Journal of Psychotherapy 38(2): 164–179.PubMed
go back to reference Money, J., and K.W. Simcoe. 1986. Acrotomophilia, sex and disability: New concepts and case report. Sexuality and Disability 7(1/2): 43–50. Money, J., and K.W. Simcoe. 1986. Acrotomophilia, sex and disability: New concepts and case report. Sexuality and Disability 7(1/2): 43–50.
go back to reference Patrone, D. 2011. Disfigured anatomies and imperfect analogies: Body integrity identity disorder and the supposed right to self-demanded amputation of healthy body parts. Journal of Medical Ethics 35: 541–545.CrossRef Patrone, D. 2011. Disfigured anatomies and imperfect analogies: Body integrity identity disorder and the supposed right to self-demanded amputation of healthy body parts. Journal of Medical Ethics 35: 541–545.CrossRef
go back to reference Person, E.S. 1980. Sexuality as the mainstay of identity: Psychoanalytic perspectives. Signs 5(4): 605–630.CrossRef Person, E.S. 1980. Sexuality as the mainstay of identity: Psychoanalytic perspectives. Signs 5(4): 605–630.CrossRef
go back to reference Rossetti, Y., G. Rode, and A. Farnè. 2005. Implicit body representations in action. In Body image and body schema, ed. H. De Preester, and V. Knockaert, 111–125. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. Rossetti, Y., G. Rode, and A. Farnè. 2005. Implicit body representations in action. In Body image and body schema, ed. H. De Preester, and V. Knockaert, 111–125. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
go back to reference Rubin, H.S. 1998. Phenomenology as method in trans studies. GLQ: A Journal of Lesbian and Gay Studies 4(2): 263–281. Rubin, H.S. 1998. Phenomenology as method in trans studies. GLQ: A Journal of Lesbian and Gay Studies 4(2): 263–281.
go back to reference Schwoebel, J., and H.B. Coslett. 2005. Evidence for multiple, distinct representations of the human body. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 17(4): 543–553.CrossRefPubMed Schwoebel, J., and H.B. Coslett. 2005. Evidence for multiple, distinct representations of the human body. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 17(4): 543–553.CrossRefPubMed
go back to reference Slatman, J., and G. Widdershoven. 2009. Being whole after amputation. The American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 9(1): 48–49.CrossRef Slatman, J., and G. Widdershoven. 2009. Being whole after amputation. The American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 9(1): 48–49.CrossRef
go back to reference Slatman, J., and G. Widdershoven. 2010. Hand transplants and bodily integrity. Body and Society 16(3): 69–92.CrossRef Slatman, J., and G. Widdershoven. 2010. Hand transplants and bodily integrity. Body and Society 16(3): 69–92.CrossRef
go back to reference Sorene, E.D., C. Heras-Palou, and F.D. Burke. 2006. Self-amputation of a healthy hand: A case of body integrity identity disorder. Journal of Hand Surgery (British and European Volume) 31B(6): 593–595. Sorene, E.D., C. Heras-Palou, and F.D. Burke. 2006. Self-amputation of a healthy hand: A case of body integrity identity disorder. Journal of Hand Surgery (British and European Volume) 31B(6): 593–595.
go back to reference Stoller, R.J. 1974. The Samuel Novey lecture–does sexual perversion exist? Johns Hopkins Medical Journal 1: 43–57. Stoller, R.J. 1974. The Samuel Novey lecture–does sexual perversion exist? Johns Hopkins Medical Journal 1: 43–57.
go back to reference Wakefield, P.L., A. Frank, and R.W. Meyers. 1977. The hobbyist–euphemism for self-mutilation and fetishism. Bulletin of the Menninger Clinic 41(6): 539–552.PubMed Wakefield, P.L., A. Frank, and R.W. Meyers. 1977. The hobbyist–euphemism for self-mutilation and fetishism. Bulletin of the Menninger Clinic 41(6): 539–552.PubMed
go back to reference Wise, T.N., and R.C. Kalyanam. 2000. Amputee fetishism and genital mutilation: Case report and literature review. Journal of Sex and Marital Therapy 2000: 339–344. Wise, T.N., and R.C. Kalyanam. 2000. Amputee fetishism and genital mutilation: Case report and literature review. Journal of Sex and Marital Therapy 2000: 339–344.
Metadata
Title
Merleau-Ponty’s sexual schema and the sexual component of body integrity identity disorder
Author
Helena De Preester
Publication date
01-05-2013
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy / Issue 2/2013
Print ISSN: 1386-7423
Electronic ISSN: 1572-8633
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-011-9367-3

Other articles of this Issue 2/2013

Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2/2013 Go to the issue