Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 1/2020

Open Access 01-03-2020 | Scientific Contribution

Health and capabilities: a conceptual clarification

Author: Per-Anders Tengland

Published in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy | Issue 1/2020

Login to get access

Abstract

There are great health disparities in the world today, both between countries and within them. This problem might be seen as related to the access to various kinds of capabilities. It is not fully clear, however, what the exact relation is between health and capabilities. Neither Amartya Sen nor Martha Nussbaum has explicitly formulated a theory of health to go with their theories of capabilities. This paper attempts to present a clarification of the conceptual relation between health and capabilities. Health, it is argued, should be seen as a holistic multi-dimensional phenomenon, made up of basic abilities and subjective well-being, and of fundamental states and processes. Using this theory, the paper shows how health is related to Nussbaum’s ten capabilities. It is argued that health, in the senses described, is a necessary part of all ten capabilities. Moreover, some of the capabilities on Nussbaum’s list, such as thinking and imagining, and practical reasoning, refer to health. Finally, it is shown that even though health is part of all capabilities, health cannot itself primarily be seen as a capability. An acceptable degree of health is required as a functioning for any theory of human flourishing to be reasonable.
Footnotes
1
This addition was suggested to me by Bengt Brülde. Personal communication 2017.
 
2
The term “practical possibilities” is used by Lennart Nordenfelt (2000, p. 65).
 
3
Note, however, that some functionings are binary, e.g., being married or not, or require mutually exclusive choices, as exemplified above.
 
4
Other capabilities have been suggested. See, for example, Wolff and De-Shalit 2013.
 
5
Neither does Jennifer Prah Ruger, who has written extensively about health and social justice (in a capabilities context), provide a definition, other than making vague references to health functioning (2010a), which is neither “well-being” nor “quality of life” (2010b, p. 42). Iain Law and Heather Widdows (2008) have also written about health and capabilities, but they have not yet provided (as far as I can see) their promised alternative theory concerning the relation between capabilities and health (p. 311, footnote 3). Sridhar Venkatapuram has, however, developed a theory of health, in relation to the capabilities theory. For a discussion of his theory, see Tengland 2016, where I initially introduced some of the ideas developed here.
 
6
I will, however, stick to writing “capability”, since all capabilities have to be combined ones, that is, every being and doing (and feeling) requires both (internal) ability and (external) opportunity (see Nussbaum 2011, p. 20).
 
7
Meaning that a fair (sometimes a considerable) degree of some of these factors is required for the capability to exist.
 
8
As one reviewer noticed, it is not always possible to make a clear distinction between basic abilities (health) and competences, since the former can become quite advanced over time (without needing “education or special training”).
 
9
Motivation, here, is about being able to form intentions and (want to) act on them (Nordenfelt 2006, p. 1463). Some might prefer to call this energy, drive, or will.
 
10
In reality, the total absence of some of these internal features will compromise a capability, for example, when severe pain (suffering) makes any kind of action impossible, or when lack of self-knowledge makes a person choose poorly.
 
11
“Unacceptable” weather and climate conditions can usually be compensated for in affluent societies.
 
12
Note, however, that the environment is important for a theory of health in another way. The environment makes actions possible (and sometimes impossible), and is a “platform” for action. Thus, to be healthy is to be able to act (or pursue one’s goals) given that the environment is acceptable, which means that in it people are expected to be able to act (or pursue their goals). See Nordenfelt 1995 (pp. 47–49), for an explication of this idea. For a detailed conceptual discussion of the boundary between what is external (environment) and internal (in relation to health), see Tengland 2015.
 
13
For a thorough analysis of the concept, we need more criteria, but these, I believe, will suffice for the present purposes.
 
14
Note that the individual should not only have acquired the abilities (etc.) in question, but also be able to use them here and now (given that the environment is acceptable), in order to be considered healthy.
 
15
Briefly, health-related, subjective well-being (and suffering) is those kinds of sensations and moods that have their immediate cause within the person (Tengland 2007, 2016), for example, feeling fit, or experiencing pain. Much more will not be said about subjective well-being, since this aspect of health is less important for the capabilities than abilities.
 
16
This claim might have to be qualified. See Tengland 2012, for a discussion of morality and health.
 
17
It is unclear why mental health is not included here. My use of the concept of “health” in discussing this capability, later in the text, will cover both physical and mental aspects. However, some of Nussbaum’s other capabilities include aspects of mental health, as I will argue.
 
18
Thus, Nussbaum uses the term health in two different ways in her theory, as a capability and as part of an internal capability, and it is unclear how they are related.
 
19
Note that in the Ottawa Charter for Health Promotion (WHO 1986), and later WHO charters, health is seen as a “resource for everyday life” (p. 1). This resource is “personal and social”, and includes “physical capacities” (p. 1). This is something quite different from (total) well-being. This idea is, however, still partly unclear, but one reasonable interpretation of it is that what the WHO calls resources are what some theoreticians call abilities (or capacities).
 
20
Nussbaum’s second capability, health, could also be interpreted to mean being able to stay free from disease, as Venkatapuram at one point suggests (2011). As such it is an obvious capability. However, we can still require (morally and politically) that the person who has this capability also be free from disease (a functioning), insofar as it is possible.
 
21
And it is probably not the view intended by Nussbaum, even though my discussion of it (Tengland 2016) in relation to Sridhar Venkatapuram’s theory (2011) made it appear a second-order one. Note, however, that for some kinds of capabilities the second-order ability might suffice. A person might, for example, want to work as a teacher, but not be able to because she has not got the appropriate education (and, thus, no first-order ability to do so, even if all other conditions needed are present). Nevertheless, the person can still have the second-order ability to acquire the education that permits her to work as a teacher. In such a case the second-order ability to work seems to suffice for us to be able to say that the capability (to work as a teacher) is present (assuming that all other conditions for it are satisfied).
 
22
Ruger makes a similar claim when she notes (in passing) that “certain aspects of health are prerequisites for other types of functioning” (2010a, p. 3). She does not, however, specify in what respect. Sen made the same observation in 2004 (p. 23).
 
23
This, as Nussbaum recognizes (in relation to children; 2011, p. 26), also goes for other skills and competences, including those learnt in primary and secondary school, for example, (generic skills such as) to write, read, count, cooperate, plan ahead, solve problems, and communicate.
 
24
This assumes that the individual has an internal potential to be fully healthy, and is not, for example, born with a dysfunction of some kind.
 
25
This means that, if people live (“freely chosen”) lives that reduce their health, many of their capabilities are likely to be reduced over time as well. Therefore, no (liberal) government can guarantee a minimal degree of capabilities for all (adults), over time.
 
26
And a certain degree of (health-related) subjective well-being (or at least absence of suffering) will contribute to the capabilities, that is, subjective well-being makes actions and goal attainment easier, whereas suffering makes things more difficult.
 
27
Assuming, once again, that the individual has the required inborn potential to develop these abilities and dispositions, and experience (health-related) subjective well-being.
 
Literature
go back to reference Brülde, B. 2000a. On How to Define the Concept of Health: A Loose Comparative Approach. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 3 (3): 305–308. Brülde, B. 2000a. On How to Define the Concept of Health: A Loose Comparative Approach. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 3 (3): 305–308.
go back to reference Brülde, B. 2000b. More on the Looser Comparative Approach to Defining ‘Health’: A Reply to Nordenfelt’s Reply. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 3 (3): 313–315. Brülde, B. 2000b. More on the Looser Comparative Approach to Defining ‘Health’: A Reply to Nordenfelt’s Reply. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 3 (3): 313–315.
go back to reference Brülde, B., and Tengland, P.-A. 2003. Hälsa och Sjukdom: En begreppslig utredning [Health and Illness: A Conceptual Investigation]. Lund: Studentlitteratur, 2003. Brülde, B., and Tengland, P.-A. 2003. Hälsa och Sjukdom: En begreppslig utredning [Health and Illness: A Conceptual Investigation]. Lund: Studentlitteratur, 2003.
go back to reference Callahan, D. 1973. The WHO Definition of ‘Health’. The Concept of Health. The Hasting Center Studies 1 (3): 77–87.CrossRef Callahan, D. 1973. The WHO Definition of ‘Health’. The Concept of Health. The Hasting Center Studies 1 (3): 77–87.CrossRef
go back to reference Cohen, G.A. 2011. Currency of Egalitarian Justice. In On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice, and Other Essays in Political Philosophy, G.A. Cohen, 3-43. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Cohen, G.A. 2011. Currency of Egalitarian Justice. In On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice, and Other Essays in Political Philosophy, G.A. Cohen, 3-43. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
go back to reference Fulford, K.W.M. 1989. Moral Theory and Medical Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Fulford, K.W.M. 1989. Moral Theory and Medical Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Law, I., and H. Widdows. 2008. Conceptualizing Health: Insights from the Capability Approach. Health Care Analysis 16: 303–314.CrossRef Law, I., and H. Widdows. 2008. Conceptualizing Health: Insights from the Capability Approach. Health Care Analysis 16: 303–314.CrossRef
go back to reference Nordenfelt, L. 1995. On the Nature of Health: An Action-Theoretic Approach. (2nd rev. ed.) Dordrecht: Kluwer. Nordenfelt, L. 1995. On the Nature of Health: An Action-Theoretic Approach. (2nd rev. ed.) Dordrecht: Kluwer.
go back to reference Nordenfelt, L. 2000. Action, Ability and Health: Essays in the Philosophy of Action and Welfare. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRef Nordenfelt, L. 2000. Action, Ability and Health: Essays in the Philosophy of Action and Welfare. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRef
go back to reference Nordenfelt, L. 2006. On Health, Ability and Activity: Comments on Some Basic Notions in the ICF. Disability and Rehabilitation 28 (23): 1461–1465.CrossRef Nordenfelt, L. 2006. On Health, Ability and Activity: Comments on Some Basic Notions in the ICF. Disability and Rehabilitation 28 (23): 1461–1465.CrossRef
go back to reference Nordenfelt, L. 2008. The Concept of Work Ability. Brussels: P.I.E. Peter Lang. Nordenfelt, L. 2008. The Concept of Work Ability. Brussels: P.I.E. Peter Lang.
go back to reference Nordenfelt, L. 2016. A Defense of the Holistic Concept of Health. In Naturalism in the Philosophy of Health: Issues and Implications, ed. É. Giroux, 209–225. Cham: Springer International Publishing.CrossRef Nordenfelt, L. 2016. A Defense of the Holistic Concept of Health. In Naturalism in the Philosophy of Health: Issues and Implications, ed. É. Giroux, 209–225. Cham: Springer International Publishing.CrossRef
go back to reference Nussbaum, M.C. 1990. Aristotelian Social Democracy. In Liberalism and the Good, ed. R.B. Douglass, G.M. Mara, and H.S. Richardson, 203–252. New York: Routledge. Nussbaum, M.C. 1990. Aristotelian Social Democracy. In Liberalism and the Good, ed. R.B. Douglass, G.M. Mara, and H.S. Richardson, 203–252. New York: Routledge.
go back to reference Nussbaum, M.C. 2000. Women and Human Development: the Capabilities Approach. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Nussbaum, M.C. 2000. Women and Human Development: the Capabilities Approach. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Nussbaum, M. 2011. Creating Capabilities. The Human Development Approach. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.CrossRef Nussbaum, M. 2011. Creating Capabilities. The Human Development Approach. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Pestana, M. 1998. Moral Virtue or Mental Health?. New York: Peter Lang Publishing. Pestana, M. 1998. Moral Virtue or Mental Health?. New York: Peter Lang Publishing.
go back to reference Pörn, I. 1984. An Equilibrium Model of Health. In Health, Disease and Causal Explanations in Medicine, ed. I. Lindahl and L. Nordenfelt, 3–9. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRef Pörn, I. 1984. An Equilibrium Model of Health. In Health, Disease and Causal Explanations in Medicine, ed. I. Lindahl and L. Nordenfelt, 3–9. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRef
go back to reference Robeyns, I. 2005. The Capability Approach: a theoretical survey. Journal of Human Development 6 (1): 93–114.CrossRef Robeyns, I. 2005. The Capability Approach: a theoretical survey. Journal of Human Development 6 (1): 93–114.CrossRef
go back to reference Ruger, J.P. 2010a. Health and Social Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ruger, J.P. 2010a. Health and Social Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Ruger, J.P. 2010b. Health Capability: Conceptualization and Operationalization. Health Policy and Ethics 100 (1): 41–49. Ruger, J.P. 2010b. Health Capability: Conceptualization and Operationalization. Health Policy and Ethics 100 (1): 41–49.
go back to reference Ryle, G. 2000 [1949]. The Concept of Mind. London: Penguin Books. Ryle, G. 2000 [1949]. The Concept of Mind. London: Penguin Books.
go back to reference Seedhouse, D. 2001. Health. Chichester: Wiley. Seedhouse, D. 2001. Health. Chichester: Wiley.
go back to reference Sen, A. 1979. The Equality of What? The Tanner Lecture on Human Values. Delivered at Stanford University, May 22, 1979, 195–220. http://hdrnet.org/43/ Accessed August 9, 2017. Sen, A. 1979. The Equality of What? The Tanner Lecture on Human Values. Delivered at Stanford University, May 22, 1979, 195–220. http://​hdrnet.​org/​43/​ Accessed August 9, 2017.
go back to reference Sen, A. 1995[1992]. Inequality reexamined. (1st Harvard University Press pbk. ed.) New York: Harvard University Press. Sen, A. 1995[1992]. Inequality reexamined. (1st Harvard University Press pbk. ed.) New York: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Sen, A. 1999. Development as Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sen, A. 1999. Development as Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Sen, A. 2004. Why health equity? In Public Health, Ethics, and Equity, ed. S. Anand, F. Peter, and A. Sen, 21–33. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sen, A. 2004. Why health equity? In Public Health, Ethics, and Equity, ed. S. Anand, F. Peter, and A. Sen, 21–33. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Taylor, G.J. 2000. Recent Developments in Alexithymia Theory and Research. Canadian Journal of Psychiatry 45 (2): 134–142.CrossRef Taylor, G.J. 2000. Recent Developments in Alexithymia Theory and Research. Canadian Journal of Psychiatry 45 (2): 134–142.CrossRef
go back to reference Tengland, P.-A. 2007. A Two-Dimensional Theory of Health. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 28 (4): 257–284.CrossRef Tengland, P.-A. 2007. A Two-Dimensional Theory of Health. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 28 (4): 257–284.CrossRef
go back to reference Tengland, P.-A. 2010. Health Promotion and Disease Prevention: Logically Different Conceptions? Health Care Analysis 18 (4): 323–341.CrossRef Tengland, P.-A. 2010. Health Promotion and Disease Prevention: Logically Different Conceptions? Health Care Analysis 18 (4): 323–341.CrossRef
go back to reference Tengland, P.-A. 2012. Health and Morality: Two Conceptually Distinct Categories? Health Care Analysis 20 (1): 66–83.CrossRef Tengland, P.-A. 2012. Health and Morality: Two Conceptually Distinct Categories? Health Care Analysis 20 (1): 66–83.CrossRef
go back to reference Tengland, P.-A. 2015. Does Amphetamine Enhance Your Health? On the Distinction Between Health and “Health-Like” Enhancements. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy. 40 (5): 484–510.CrossRef Tengland, P.-A. 2015. Does Amphetamine Enhance Your Health? On the Distinction Between Health and “Health-Like” Enhancements. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy. 40 (5): 484–510.CrossRef
go back to reference Tengland, P.-A. 2016. Venkatapuram’s Capability Theory of Health: A Critical Discussion. Bioethics 30 (1): 8–18.CrossRef Tengland, P.-A. 2016. Venkatapuram’s Capability Theory of Health: A Critical Discussion. Bioethics 30 (1): 8–18.CrossRef
go back to reference Venkatapuram, S. 2011. Health Justice. Cambridge: Polity Press. Venkatapuram, S. 2011. Health Justice. Cambridge: Polity Press.
go back to reference Whitbeck, C. 1981. A theory of health. In Concepts of Health and Disease: Interdisciplinary Perspectives, ed. A.L. Caplan, T.H. Engelhardt Jr., and J.J. McCartney, 611–626. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Whitbeck, C. 1981. A theory of health. In Concepts of Health and Disease: Interdisciplinary Perspectives, ed. A.L. Caplan, T.H. Engelhardt Jr., and J.J. McCartney, 611–626. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
go back to reference Wolff, J., and A. De-Shalit. 2013. Disadvantage. New York: Oxford University Press. Wolff, J., and A. De-Shalit. 2013. Disadvantage. New York: Oxford University Press.
Metadata
Title
Health and capabilities: a conceptual clarification
Author
Per-Anders Tengland
Publication date
01-03-2020
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy / Issue 1/2020
Print ISSN: 1386-7423
Electronic ISSN: 1572-8633
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-019-09902-w

Other articles of this Issue 1/2020

Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 1/2020 Go to the issue

Scientific Contribution

Autism, autonomy, and authenticity