Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Health Care Analysis 1/2015

01-03-2015 | Original Article

Paternalism and Utilitarianism in Research with Human Participants

Author: David B. Resnik

Published in: Health Care Analysis | Issue 1/2015

Login to get access

Abstract

In this article I defend a rule utilitarian approach to paternalistic policies in research with human participants. Some rules that restrict individual autonomy can be justified on the grounds that they help to maximize the overall balance of benefits over risks in research. The consequences that should be considered when formulating policy include not only likely impacts on research participants, but also impacts on investigators, institutions, sponsors, and the scientific community. The public reaction to adverse events in research (such as significant injury to participants or death) is a crucial concern that must be taken into account when assessing the consequences of different policy options, because public backlash can lead to outcomes that have a negative impact on science, such as cuts in funding, overly restrictive regulation and oversight, and reduced willingness of individuals to participate in research. I argue that concern about the public reaction to adverse events justifies some restrictions on the risks that competent, adult volunteers can face in research that offers them no significant benefits. The paternalism defended here is not pure, because it involves restrictions on the rights of investigators in order to protect participants. It also has a mixed rationale, because individual autonomy may be restricted not only to protect participants from harm but also to protect other stakeholders. Utility is not the sole justification for paternalistic research policies, since other considerations, such as justice and respect for individual rights/autonomy, must also be taken into account.
Literature
1.
go back to reference Arneson, R. (1989). Paternalism, utility and fairness. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 170, 409–423. Arneson, R. (1989). Paternalism, utility and fairness. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 170, 409–423.
2.
go back to reference Brandt, R. (1998) A Theory of the good and the right (revised ed). New York: Prometheus Books. Brandt, R. (1998) A Theory of the good and the right (revised ed). New York: Prometheus Books.
4.
go back to reference Department of Health and Human Services. (2009). Protection of Human Subjects, 45 CFR 46. Department of Health and Human Services. (2009). Protection of Human Subjects, 45 CFR 46.
7.
go back to reference Edwards, S. J., & Wilson, J. (2012). Hard paternalism, fairness and clinical research: Why not? Bioethics, 26, 68–75.PubMedCrossRef Edwards, S. J., & Wilson, J. (2012). Hard paternalism, fairness and clinical research: Why not? Bioethics, 26, 68–75.PubMedCrossRef
9.
go back to reference Feinberg, J. (1986). Harm to self. New York: Oxford University Press. Feinberg, J. (1986). Harm to self. New York: Oxford University Press.
11.
go back to reference Grady, C., Dickert, N., Jawetz, T., Gensler, G., & Emanuel, E. (2005). An analysis of U.S. practices of paying research participants. Contemporary Clinical Trials, 26, 365–375.PubMedCrossRef Grady, C., Dickert, N., Jawetz, T., Gensler, G., & Emanuel, E. (2005). An analysis of U.S. practices of paying research participants. Contemporary Clinical Trials, 26, 365–375.PubMedCrossRef
12.
go back to reference Jansen, L. A., & Wall, S. (2009). Paternalism and fairness in clinical research. Bioethics, 23, 172–182.PubMedCrossRef Jansen, L. A., & Wall, S. (2009). Paternalism and fairness in clinical research. Bioethics, 23, 172–182.PubMedCrossRef
13.
go back to reference Jonas, H. (1969). Philosophical reflections on experimenting with human subjects. Daedalus, 98, 219–247. Jonas, H. (1969). Philosophical reflections on experimenting with human subjects. Daedalus, 98, 219–247.
14.
go back to reference Jonsen, A. (1988). The birth of bioethics. New York: Oxford University Press. Jonsen, A. (1988). The birth of bioethics. New York: Oxford University Press.
15.
go back to reference Kleinig, J. (1983). Paternalism. Manchester: Manchester University Press. Kleinig, J. (1983). Paternalism. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
16.
go back to reference Lederer, S. (2008). Walter reed and the yellow fever experiments. In E. Emanuel, C. Grady, R. Crouch, R. Lie, F. Miller, & D. Wendler (Eds.), The Oxford textbook of clinical research ethics (pp. 9–17). New York: Oxford University Press. Lederer, S. (2008). Walter reed and the yellow fever experiments. In E. Emanuel, C. Grady, R. Crouch, R. Lie, F. Miller, & D. Wendler (Eds.), The Oxford textbook of clinical research ethics (pp. 9–17). New York: Oxford University Press.
17.
go back to reference Mill, J. S. (1869) [1978]. On liberty. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company. Mill, J. S. (1869) [1978]. On liberty. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.
18.
go back to reference Miller, F. G., & Wertheimer, A. (2007). Facing up to paternalism in research ethics. Hastings Center Report, 37(3), 24–34.PubMedCrossRef Miller, F. G., & Wertheimer, A. (2007). Facing up to paternalism in research ethics. Hastings Center Report, 37(3), 24–34.PubMedCrossRef
19.
go back to reference National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. (1979). The Belmont report: Ethical principles and guidelines for the protection of human subjects of research. Washington, DC: Department of Health, Education, and Welfare. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. (1979). The Belmont report: Ethical principles and guidelines for the protection of human subjects of research. Washington, DC: Department of Health, Education, and Welfare.
22.
go back to reference Resnik, D. B. (2007). Are the new EPA regulations concerning intentional exposure studies with children overprotective? IRB, 29(5), 5–7. Resnik, D. B. (2007). Are the new EPA regulations concerning intentional exposure studies with children overprotective? IRB, 29(5), 5–7.
24.
go back to reference Shamoo, A. S., & Resnik, D. B. (2009). Responsible conduct of research (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Shamoo, A. S., & Resnik, D. B. (2009). Responsible conduct of research (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
25.
go back to reference Smart, J. J. C., & Williams, B. (1973). Utilitarianism: For and against. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Smart, J. J. C., & Williams, B. (1973). Utilitarianism: For and against. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
26.
go back to reference Steinbrook, R. (2002). Protecting research subjects—the Crisis at Johns Hopkins. New England Journal of Medicine, 346, 716–720.PubMedCrossRef Steinbrook, R. (2002). Protecting research subjects—the Crisis at Johns Hopkins. New England Journal of Medicine, 346, 716–720.PubMedCrossRef
27.
go back to reference Wertheimer, A. (2008). Rethinking the ethics of clinical research: Widening the lens. New York: Oxford University Press. Wertheimer, A. (2008). Rethinking the ethics of clinical research: Widening the lens. New York: Oxford University Press.
29.
go back to reference Yarborough, M., & Sharp, R. (2009). Public trust and research a decade later: What have we learned since Jesse Gelsinger’s death? Molecular Genetics and Metabolism, 97, 4–5.PubMedCrossRef Yarborough, M., & Sharp, R. (2009). Public trust and research a decade later: What have we learned since Jesse Gelsinger’s death? Molecular Genetics and Metabolism, 97, 4–5.PubMedCrossRef
Metadata
Title
Paternalism and Utilitarianism in Research with Human Participants
Author
David B. Resnik
Publication date
01-03-2015
Publisher
Springer US
Published in
Health Care Analysis / Issue 1/2015
Print ISSN: 1065-3058
Electronic ISSN: 1573-3394
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-012-0233-0

Other articles of this Issue 1/2015

Health Care Analysis 1/2015 Go to the issue