Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Health Care Analysis 4/2006

01-12-2006 | Original Article

Solidarity: A (New) Ethic for Global Health Policy

Author: Shawn H. E. Harmon

Published in: Health Care Analysis | Issue 4/2006

Login to get access

Abstract

This article explores solidarity as an ethical concept underpinning rules in the global health context. First, it considers the theoretical conceptualisation of the value and some specific duties it supports (ie: its expression in the broadest sense and its derivative action-guiding duties). Second, it considers the manifestation of solidarity in two international regulatory instruments. It concludes that, although solidarity is represented in these instruments, it is often incidental. This fact, their emphasis on other values and their internal weaknesses diminishes the action-guiding impact of the solidarity rules. The global health and human subject research scene needs a completely new instrument specifically directed at means by which solidarity can be achieved, and a reformed infrastructure dedicated to realising that value.
Footnotes
1
Biotechnology is here used to denote the application of new and emerging technologies to the study of living organisms or that uses living organisms or derivatives thereof to produce or modify (health) products and services. See the definition in the Convention on Biological Diversity (1992), signed by 168 states, as well as those at www.mayominnesotapartnership.org/glossary.htm and www.uni-hohenheim.de/biotech/eng/def_biotech.htm.
 
2
Biotechnological advances will increase the variety and predictability of diagnostic processes, widen the scope and effectiveness of treatment processes, and generally alter the social setting within which medicine is practiced [50, 51].
 
3
Attempts to define these and other values and to measure the propriety of tomorrow’s biotechnologies have been undertaken within the rubric of various moral approaches, including principlism, virtuism, feminism, etc. For the purposes of this paper, no particular “approach” or overarching “theory” of rights or morality is espoused.
 
4
In African traditionalism, note the maxim simunye (we are one; unity strength). In Buddhism, Hinduism and Christianity, note concepts of brotherhood and interconnectedness. In Judaism, note clal yisrael (unity despite differences) and brit (the covenant which binds Jews to one another and to God, and the fostering of reut or “neighbourliness”). In Islam, note tawhid (unity and oneness of humanity).
 
5
In African traditionalism, note the widely held maxim, umuntu ngumuntu ngabantu (to be human is to affirm one’s humanity by recognizing the humanity of others). In Buddhism, note the admonition against excess. In Confucianism, note the emphasis on love of life and mutual respect. In Hinduism and Christianity, note concepts of reciprocity. In Judaism, note arevut (mutual obligation). In Islam, note hubb (love), rahma (mercy/compassion).
 
6
In some African traditions, note shosholoza (working as a team; group spirit in adversity) and the shared responsibility of dialogue and cooperative action. In some Asia traditions, note kalayanamitra (friends helping friends). In Buddhism, note concepts of enduring sacrifice in others’ interests. In Confucianism, note concepts of duties and action toward others. In Hinduism, note da da da (give and be merciful) and concepts of obligation to others. In Judaism, note kiruv (reaching out, partnering with humanity) and tzedaka (duties to help the poor). In Christianity, note John 15:13 (self-sacrifice) and Mark 10:21, Luke 6:20 and John 3:17 (mutual assistance, often in relation to the poor). In Islam, note zakat (obligation to give to the poor), sadaqah (charity/altruism), and concepts of ‘adl (justice) and wast (equilibrium) which underpin principles condemning exploitation and the isolation of oneself from the rest of humanity.
 
7
J. Habermas [47] Zur Bestimmung der Moral (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1986), uses the term “intersubjectivity.”
 
8
Only by situating the individual within society can we determine whether we have obligations toward one another as citizens of a community [60].
 
9
The income of the richest 20% of humanity is 80x that of the poorest 20%, and more than 2 billion people live on less than US$2 per day ([9], at 112). See also UNDP, Human Development Report 1999 (Geneva: [101], at http://hdr.undp.org/reports/global/1999/en/, and R. Falk, Predatory Globalization: A Critique (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1999).
 
10
Global population has risen from 4,452,645,562 (1980), to 5,282,765,827 (1990), to 6,081,527,896 (2000), to 6,460,560,374 (2005): see www.census.gov/ipc/www/worldpop.html (Aug. 16/05). It is expected to rise to 9.1 billion by 2050: see www.overpopulation.org/faq.html (Aug. 16/05).
 
11
Communicable diseases, which do not respect borders, continue to be the leading loss of human life: L. Garrett, The Coming Plague: Newly Emerging Diseases in a World Out of Balance (NY: Farrar, Strauss & Giroux, 1994). Contemporary examples of the mobility of infectious diseases are the SARS outbreak of 2003 and the more recent Avian Influenza pandemic; in a short time, it spread through multiple countries, resulting in tens of thousands of bird deaths and 63 human deaths: www.who.int/csr/disease/ avianinfluenze/country/case_table_2005_11_07/index.html (Nov. 8/05). For more on this, see www.fao.org/ ag/againfo/subjects/en/health/diseases-cards/special_avian.html, and http://europa/eu/int/comm/food/animal/ diseases/controlmeasures/avian/index_en.htm.
 
12
Whereas the global population increases by approximately 3,000 every 20 min (+/−), one or more species of animal or plant life becomes extinct (some 27,000 species per year): www.overpopulation.org/faq.html (Aug. 16/05). Freshwater consumption has increased 6× in the last 100 years; 5 million people die annually from diarrhoea due to polluted water; 20% of the world’s freshwater fish have disappeared or are endangered; some 63% of all species have been lost in the last 100 years and extinctions are occurring at increased rates; some 80% of forests have been cut worldwide and 40% of the remainder are threatened [84]. Extinction rates are estimated at between 1,000 and 10,000 times greater than they would be naturally [93]. Some 40% of the world’s forests are threatened by mining, and 25% of the world’s mammals and 11% of the world’s birds are at risk of extinction due to population growth and loss of habitat: Population Connection, at www.populationconnection.org/factoids/ (Aug. 16/05).
 
13
Health and security are linked [102]. Increasingly vicious, ethnic-based wars in poor nations cause massive human suffering, social disruption, population displacement and loss of natural resources [26]. Some 90% of modern war victims are civilians, mostly women and children: Population Connection, at www.populationconnection.org/factoids/ (Aug. 16/05).
 
14
Life expectancy by region has been reported as follows: Africa—46 (M), 48 (F); Americas—71 (M), 77 (F); South-East Asia—61 (M), 64 (F); Europe—68 (M), 77 (F); Eastern Mediterranean—61 (M), 64 (F); Western Pacific—70 (M), 74 (F). The countries with the lowest life expectancy rates and healthy life expectancy rates are African. Compared to life expectancy in the UK of 76 (M) and 81 (F), life expectancy rates in Lesotho are 35 (M) and 40 (F), Swaziland are 33 (M) and 36 (F), and Zimbabwe are 37 (M) and 36 (F). ([103], at 13).
 
15
See Article 12 of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966). Also see the Jakarta Declaration on Health Promotion into the 21 Century (1997), the People’s Health Charter (2000), and J. Mann et al. (eds.), Health and Human Rights (NY: Routledge, 1999).
 
16
Of 1,223 new drugs developed between 1975 and 1997, only 11 were for the treatment of tropical diseases, which are some of the largest killers [94]. In 1993, cancer research spending in the UK alone was US$200 million, whereas malaria research spending was US$84 million worldwide ([80], at 23). Over 40 million people, mostly in resource-poor developing countries, have HIV/AIDS, and even those few that benefit from drug trials receive very little follow up treatment post-trial [6, 59).
 
17
The commodification of the intellectual property regime has permitted the pharmaceutical industry pursue artificial improvements (rather than truly new products) while keeping prices elevated. [24].
 
18
See Preamble, WHO Constitution (1948). Every country in the world is a party to at least one treaty addressing health-related rights, including the right to health: see www.who.int/hhr/en/ (Aug. 26/05).
 
19
For an example such claims in a legal instrument, see the Convention on Biomedicine (1997).
 
20
Internationally, see Article 12 (privacy, family, home, correspondence) of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948), and Article 17 (privacy, family, home, correspondence) of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966). Regionally, see Article 8 (privacy, family, home, correspondence) of the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (1950). In the UK, see Article 8 (privacy, family, home, correspondence), Part I of Schedule 1 of the Human Rights Act 1998 (UK) 1998, c. 42.
 
21
See Articles 2 (entitlement to rights without distinction) and 7 (no discrimination) of the UDHR (1948), Articles 2 (no distinctions on named grounds), 3 (equality of men and women), 26 (no discrimination) and 27 (minority rights) of the ICCPR (1966), Article 14 (no discrimination) of the ECHR (1950), and Article 14 (no discrimination), Part I of Schedule 1 of the HRA 1998.
 
22
See Articles 18 (thought, conscience, religion) and 19 (opinion, expression) of the UDHR (1948), Articles 18 (thought, conscience, religion) and 19 (opinion) of ICCPR (1966), Articles 9 (thought, conscience, religion) and 10 (expression) of the ECHR (1950), and Articles 9 (thought, conscience, religion) and 10 (expression), Part I of Schedule 1 of the HRA 1998.
 
23
See Articles 13 (movement) and 14 (asylum) of the UDHR (1948), Article 12 (movement) of the ICCPR (1966), Articles 2 (movement) and 3 (no expulsion) of Protocol 4 (1963) of the ECHR (1950).
 
24
See Articles 3 (life, liberty, security of the person), 8 (arrest, detention, exile), 10 (fair public hearing) of the UDHR (1948), Articles 6 (right to life) and 9 (liberty, security, fair trial) of the ICCPR (1966), Articles 5 (liberty, security) and 6 (fair trial) of the ECHR (1950), and Articles 5 (liberty, security) and 6 (fair trial), Part I of Schedule 1 of the HRA 1998.
 
25
See Chadwick and Berg [23], Callahan [18], Benatar [10], and others, who suggest that non-autonomy interests, when considered at all, are used to lead straight back to autonomy and individualism. Indeed, it has been claimed that autonomy is the primary if not the only interest worthy of protection [43].
 
26
In 1998, the USA, with approximately 4% of the world’s population, generated some 22% of the world’s green-house-effect causing CO2 emissions: Your Planet Earth (2000), at www.yourplanetearth.org (Aug. 17/05).
 
27
From 1982–1990, southern countries received US$927 million in aid, grants, trade credits, direct private investment and loans, but paid out US$1.3 trillion in interest and principal. From 1991–1998, grants to developing countries went down from US$35 billion to US$23 billion [9].
 
28
UNESCO [97], at 10, has suggested that solidarity is an ethical imperative of growing importance given ideals of collective social protection and fair opportunity and the existence of serious inequalities in access to healthcare worldwide. Benatar et al. [9], claim that solidarity is the most important global health ethic and must be applied on a global basis. See also Mayor [71].
 
29
Indeed, the UN General Assembly has called for states to take measures to ensure that the results of scientific/technological advances are used for, and only for, the benefit of humankind: General Assembly Resolution 48/140, UN GAOR, 48th Sess., Supp. No. 49, UN Doc. A/48/49 (vol. 1) (1994).
 
30
The necessity for such collaborations is identified in the Bangkok Declaration (2000). See also Tollman [96], and Benatar and Singer [8]. The idea of capacity building in less enabled states is being pursued within Europe through the EU Framework Programs and the work of the EST, which encourages joint projects, multi-state funding and international peer review: Conference, “Towards a European Research Area” (Oct. 19–21, 2005).
 
31
For more on the inequity of the current distribution of medical resources, see www.pharmaportal.com, www.globalforumhealth.org.
 
32
See Article 27 of the UDHR (1948), Article 15 of the ICESCR (1966), and Articles 1, 2 and 7 of the Convention on Biological Diversity (1992), which espouse sharing technology so as to exploit and preserve biological/genetic resources, and Articles 12, 15, 16, 17 and 18 of the same Convention, which envision sharing knowledge, research and biotechnology with developing states.
 
33
Social and ethical accounting, auditing and reporting provides a practical mechanism for companies to integrate new patterns of civil accountability and governance with a business success model focused on deepening stakeholder relationships around both financial and non-financial interests, and that effective methods for doing so are evolving ([Zadek, 105], at 1428).
 
34
Cassel and Young [21], argue that over-reliance on autonomy-based consent in NHS research hinders the public good. Both Boter et al. [15], and Dawson [32], also describe research projects where obtaining prior informed consent was not appropriate. Bhagwanjee et al. [11], offer four conditions for foregoing consent.
 
35
It is at this stage that the differences between solidarity and altruism become apparent. Legislators are reluctant to legally impose altruism, rightfully likening that concept to a personal sense of unselfish concern for others which cannot be compelled. Its very definition implies the observance of conduct that is not demanded. I would suggest that solidarity is more active and, with its derivative duties, more appropriately compellable.
 
36
The Helsinki Declaration, adopted in 1964 and most recently revised in 2000 (with two subsequent “Clarifications”), was a response to the abuses perpetrated in Nazi Germany against involuntary human research subjects in the name of biomedical science. These abuses prompted the Nuremberg Trials and the subsequent Nuremberg Code, drafted by the US judges who tried the cases.
 
37
The CIOMS Guidelines, adopted in 1982 and most recently revised in 2002, is primarily concerned with the application of the Helsinki Declaration principles in the context of multinational research implicating developing countries. It was largely a response to the special concerns arising from the HIV/AIDS pandemic and research activities related thereto: see www.cioms.ch/guidelines_nov_2002_blurb.htm (Sep. 8/05).
 
38
Nonetheless, and despite their moral authority, universal compliance with them has been questioned ([69, 98], at 22–23).
 
39
Although it has been accused of representing the “doers” of research and not the “researched,” and of adopting an under-inclusive revision procedure [5]. The WMA [104] is comprised of representatives from approximately 80 national medical associations from all continents: see www.wma.net/e/about/index.htm (Sep. 2/05). CIOMS, founded under the auspices of the WHO and UNESCO in 1949, is comprised of 18 international organizations, 17 national representatives, and 25 associate members: see www.cioms.ch/frame_current_membership.htm (Sep. 7/05).
 
40
This interpretation is arrived at and lamented by Harris [52], and by Forster et al. [39], who also cite the removal of the distinction between therapeutic and non-therapeutic research in the new version as a weakness. However, Weijer and Anderson [100], state that the previous distinction between therapeutic and non-therapeutic research was a major flaw.
 
41
Indeed, there were almost immediate calls to revise Article 30, but the pressure to do so has thus far been resisted [40].
 
42
Christie [25], argues that something is either moral or not and the same ethical rules should apply wherever research is conducted.
 
43
Bastian [5], considers this a “limited approach” to the concept of access to research, which is absent in the Helsinki Declaration.
 
44
Guidelines 14 (children), 15 (mental/behavioural disorder), 16 (women) and 17 (pregnant women) offer guidance in specific circumstances. For more on vulnerability, see Macklin [70], and Zion et al. [106].
 
45
Calls for a shift from “adversarial national security paradigms” towards a more inclusive, compromising, multilateral and engaging “cooperative global security paradigms” have already been made [9, 74, 75, 99].
 
46
Although basic needs are common, disease burdens are not equally shared and capacities are not evenly enjoyed, so specific needs may be heterogeneous. As such, different communities will have different levels and particulars of needs (and responsibilities). This does not negate the validity of the statement that our needs draw us together, particularly now that global mobility is facilitating disease mobility.
 
47
One need only look at the impact of the SARS outbreak in China, which spread across the ocean to Canada. For more on that outbreak, see www.who.int/topics/sars/en/, and D. Macer (ed.) [67], at 24.
 
Literature
1.
go back to reference Angell M (2000) The pharmaceutical industry—To whom is it accountable. NEJM 352: 1902–1904CrossRef Angell M (2000) The pharmaceutical industry—To whom is it accountable. NEJM 352: 1902–1904CrossRef
2.
go back to reference Arts W, Verburg R (2002) Modernisation, solidarity and care in Europe: The sociologist’s tale. In: ter Meulen R et al. (eds) Solidarity in health and social care in Europe. Springer, UK, pp 15–40 Arts W, Verburg R (2002) Modernisation, solidarity and care in Europe: The sociologist’s tale. In: ter Meulen R et al. (eds) Solidarity in health and social care in Europe. Springer, UK, pp 15–40
3.
go back to reference Ashcroft R et al (2000) Solidarity, society and the welfare state in the United Kingdom. Health Care Anal 8: 377–394PubMedCrossRef Ashcroft R et al (2000) Solidarity, society and the welfare state in the United Kingdom. Health Care Anal 8: 377–394PubMedCrossRef
4.
go back to reference Azariah J (2003) Asian Bioethics in global society. In: Sang-yong S, Young-Mo K, Macer D (eds) Asian bioethics in the 21st century. Eubios, NZ, pp 219–223 Azariah J (2003) Asian Bioethics in global society. In: Sang-yong S, Young-Mo K, Macer D (eds) Asian bioethics in the 21st century. Eubios, NZ, pp 219–223
5.
go back to reference Bastian H (2001) What are the effects of the fifth revision of the declaration of Helsinki? Gains and losses for rights of consumers and research participants. BMJ 323: 1417–1423PubMedCrossRef Bastian H (2001) What are the effects of the fifth revision of the declaration of Helsinki? Gains and losses for rights of consumers and research participants. BMJ 323: 1417–1423PubMedCrossRef
6.
go back to reference Benatar S (1998) Global disparities in health and human rights. AJPH 88: 395–400 Benatar S (1998) Global disparities in health and human rights. AJPH 88: 395–400
7.
go back to reference Benatar S (2001) Distributive justice and clinical trials in the Third World. Theo Med 22: 169–176CrossRef Benatar S (2001) Distributive justice and clinical trials in the Third World. Theo Med 22: 169–176CrossRef
8.
9.
go back to reference Benatar S, Daar A, Singer P (2003) Global health ethics: The rationale for mutual caring. Int Aff 79: 107–138CrossRef Benatar S, Daar A, Singer P (2003) Global health ethics: The rationale for mutual caring. Int Aff 79: 107–138CrossRef
10.
go back to reference Benatar S (2004) Blinkered bioethics. JME 30: 291–292 Benatar S (2004) Blinkered bioethics. JME 30: 291–292
11.
go back to reference Bhagwanjee S et al (1997) Why we did not seek informed consent before testing patients for HIV. BMJ 314: 1082 Bhagwanjee S et al (1997) Why we did not seek informed consent before testing patients for HIV. BMJ 314: 1082
12.
go back to reference Bhutta Z (2002) Ethics in international health research: A perspective from the developing world. WHO Bull 80: 114–120 Bhutta Z (2002) Ethics in international health research: A perspective from the developing world. WHO Bull 80: 114–120
14.
go back to reference Bond P (1999) Globalization, pharmaceutical pricing and South African health policy. IJHS 29(4): 765–792 Bond P (1999) Globalization, pharmaceutical pricing and South African health policy. IJHS 29(4): 765–792
15.
go back to reference Boter H et al (2004) Patients’ evaluation of informed consent to postponed information: Cohort study. BMJ 329: 86PubMedCrossRef Boter H et al (2004) Patients’ evaluation of informed consent to postponed information: Cohort study. BMJ 329: 86PubMedCrossRef
16.
go back to reference Brownsword R (2005) Biotechnology and rights: Where are we coming from and where are we going?. In: Klang M, Murray A (eds) Human rights in the digital age. Glasshouse, London, pp 219–234 Brownsword R (2005) Biotechnology and rights: Where are we coming from and where are we going?. In: Klang M, Murray A (eds) Human rights in the digital age. Glasshouse, London, pp 219–234
17.
go back to reference Bruce A, Tait J (2003) Interests, values and biotechnological risk. INNOGEN Working Paper 7, at www.innogen.ac.uk/publications/ Bruce A, Tait J (2003) Interests, values and biotechnological risk. INNOGEN Working Paper 7, at www.innogen.ac.uk/publications/
18.
go back to reference Callahan D (2003) Principlism and communitarianism. JME 29: 287–291 Callahan D (2003) Principlism and communitarianism. JME 29: 287–291
19.
go back to reference Caplan A et al. (1999) The human genome project: What is immoral about eugenics? BMJ 319: 1284PubMed Caplan A et al. (1999) The human genome project: What is immoral about eugenics? BMJ 319: 1284PubMed
20.
go back to reference Carpenter W et al (2003) The declaration of Helsinki and clinical trials: A focus on placebo-controlled trials in Schizophrenia. AJ Psychiatry 160: 356–362CrossRef Carpenter W et al (2003) The declaration of Helsinki and clinical trials: A focus on placebo-controlled trials in Schizophrenia. AJ Psychiatry 160: 356–362CrossRef
21.
go back to reference Cassel J, Young A (2002) Why we should not seek individual informed consent for participation in heath service research. BMJ 328: 313–317 Cassel J, Young A (2002) Why we should not seek individual informed consent for participation in heath service research. BMJ 328: 313–317
22.
go back to reference Chadwick R (1999) The Iceland database: Do modern times need modern sagas? BMJ 319: 441–444PubMed Chadwick R (1999) The Iceland database: Do modern times need modern sagas? BMJ 319: 441–444PubMed
23.
go back to reference Chadwick R, Berg K (2001) Solidarity and equality: New ethical frameworks for genetic databases. Nat Rev Genet 2: 318–321PubMedCrossRef Chadwick R, Berg K (2001) Solidarity and equality: New ethical frameworks for genetic databases. Nat Rev Genet 2: 318–321PubMedCrossRef
24.
go back to reference Chee Khoon C (2003) Commodification and market-driven biomedical research. At www.biopolitics-berlin2003.org Chee Khoon C (2003) Commodification and market-driven biomedical research. At www.biopolitics-berlin2003.org
26.
27.
go back to reference Commentary on Guideline 3, at www.cioms.ch/guidelines_nov_2002_blurb.htm Commentary on Guideline 3, at www.cioms.ch/guidelines_nov_2002_blurb.htm
28.
go back to reference Commission on Intellectual Property Rights (2002) Integrating intellectual property rights and development policy. CIPR, London Commission on Intellectual Property Rights (2002) Integrating intellectual property rights and development policy. CIPR, London
29.
go back to reference Corrigan O (2004) Informed consent: The contradictory ethical safeguards in pharmacogenetics. In: Tutton R, Corrigan O (eds) Genetic databases: Socio-ethical issues in the collection and use of DNA. Routledge, London, pp 78–96 Corrigan O (2004) Informed consent: The contradictory ethical safeguards in pharmacogenetics. In: Tutton R, Corrigan O (eds) Genetic databases: Socio-ethical issues in the collection and use of DNA. Routledge, London, pp 78–96
30.
go back to reference Crawley F, Hoet F (1999) Ethics and law: The declaration of Helsinki Under Discussion. Bull ME 150: 9–12 Crawley F, Hoet F (1999) Ethics and law: The declaration of Helsinki Under Discussion. Bull ME 150: 9–12
31.
go back to reference Davis M (1997) Constitutionalism and political culture: The debate over human rights and Asian values. Harv HRJ 10: 109–148 Davis M (1997) Constitutionalism and political culture: The debate over human rights and Asian values. Harv HRJ 10: 109–148
32.
go back to reference Dawson A (2004) Methodological reasons for not gaining prior informed consent are sometimes justified. BMJ 329: 87PubMedCrossRef Dawson A (2004) Methodological reasons for not gaining prior informed consent are sometimes justified. BMJ 329: 87PubMedCrossRef
33.
go back to reference de Bary W (1998) Asian values and human rights: A confucian communitarian perspective. Harvard U. Press, London de Bary W (1998) Asian values and human rights: A confucian communitarian perspective. Harvard U. Press, London
34.
go back to reference Deutsch E, Taupitz J (1999) Freedom of control and biomedical research. Bull ME 150: 22–24 Deutsch E, Taupitz J (1999) Freedom of control and biomedical research. Bull ME 150: 22–24
35.
go back to reference Donne J, Meditation XVII (1624) Devotions upon emergent occasions. At http: //en.wikipedia.org/ wiki/john_donne Donne J, Meditation XVII (1624) Devotions upon emergent occasions. At http: //en.wikipedia.org/ wiki/john_donne
36.
go back to reference Eaton L (2005) Nuffield council calls for ethics framework for developing world research. BMJ 330: 618PubMedCrossRef Eaton L (2005) Nuffield council calls for ethics framework for developing world research. BMJ 330: 618PubMedCrossRef
37.
go back to reference Editorial (1999) The Helsinki declaration—Nothing to declare. Lancet 353: 1285CrossRef Editorial (1999) The Helsinki declaration—Nothing to declare. Lancet 353: 1285CrossRef
38.
go back to reference Elazar D (1999) Jewish civilization and polity in a globalized world: A new vision for organized jewry. At www.jcpa.org/dje/articles2/vision99.htm Elazar D (1999) Jewish civilization and polity in a globalized world: A new vision for organized jewry. At www.jcpa.org/dje/articles2/vision99.htm
39.
go back to reference Forster H et al (2001) The 2000 revision of the declaration of Helsinki: A step forward or more confusion? Lancet 358: 1449–1453PubMedCrossRef Forster H et al (2001) The 2000 revision of the declaration of Helsinki: A step forward or more confusion? Lancet 358: 1449–1453PubMedCrossRef
40.
41.
go back to reference Fukuyama F (2002) Our posthuman future. Profile, London Fukuyama F (2002) Our posthuman future. Profile, London
42.
go back to reference Gevers J et al (2002) Popular support for health care in Europe: Review of the evidence of cross-national surveys. In: ter Meulen R, et al (eds) Solidarity in health and social care in Europe. Springer, UK, pp 41–76 Gevers J et al (2002) Popular support for health care in Europe: Review of the evidence of cross-national surveys. In: ter Meulen R, et al (eds) Solidarity in health and social care in Europe. Springer, UK, pp 41–76
43.
go back to reference Gillon R (2003) Ethics needs principles—Four can encompass the rest—and respect for autonomy should be ‘first among equals’.” JME 29: 307–312 Gillon R (2003) Ethics needs principles—Four can encompass the rest—and respect for autonomy should be ‘first among equals’.” JME 29: 307–312
44.
go back to reference Global Forum for Health Research (2004) 10/90 Report on health research 2003–2004. GFHR, Geneva Global Forum for Health Research (2004) 10/90 Report on health research 2003–2004. GFHR, Geneva
45.
go back to reference Goldsand G et al (2001) Bioethics for clinicians: Jewish bioethics. CMAJ 164: 219PubMed Goldsand G et al (2001) Bioethics for clinicians: Jewish bioethics. CMAJ 164: 219PubMed
46.
go back to reference Gwatkin D (2000) Health inequalities and the health of the poor: What do we know? What can we do? Bull WHO 78: 3–18PubMed Gwatkin D (2000) Health inequalities and the health of the poor: What do we know? What can we do? Bull WHO 78: 3–18PubMed
47.
go back to reference Habermas J (2003) The future of human nature. Polity Press, Cambridge Habermas J (2003) The future of human nature. Polity Press, Cambridge
48.
go back to reference Halevi H The thirteen principles of Jewish medical ethics. At www.jewishpeople.net/jewmedet.htm Halevi H The thirteen principles of Jewish medical ethics. At www.jewishpeople.net/jewmedet.htm
49.
go back to reference Halsey N et al (1999) Ethics and international research. BMJ 315: 965–966 Halsey N et al (1999) Ethics and international research. BMJ 315: 965–966
50.
go back to reference Harmon S (2005a) The significance of UNESCO’s universal declaration on the human genome and human rights. SCRIPT-ed 2(1): 18–47, at www.law.ed.ac.uk/ahrb/script-ed/vol2-1/harmon.pdf Harmon S (2005a) The significance of UNESCO’s universal declaration on the human genome and human rights. SCRIPT-ed 2(1): 18–47, at www.law.ed.ac.uk/ahrb/script-ed/vol2-1/harmon.pdf
51.
go back to reference Harmon S (2005b) Regulation of human genomics & genetic biotechnology: Risks, values and analytical criteria. INNOGEN Working Paper 40, at www.innogen.ac.uk/publications/ Harmon S (2005b) Regulation of human genomics & genetic biotechnology: Risks, values and analytical criteria. INNOGEN Working Paper 40, at www.innogen.ac.uk/publications/
52.
go back to reference Harris J (2005) Scientific research is a moral duty. JME 31: 242–248 Harris J (2005) Scientific research is a moral duty. JME 31: 242–248
53.
go back to reference Hayry M (2003) European values in bioethics: Why, what and how to be used? Theo Med 24: 1999–214 Hayry M (2003) European values in bioethics: Why, what and how to be used? Theo Med 24: 1999–214
54.
go back to reference Hirsch L, Guess H (2001) Some clauses will hinder development of new drugs and vaccines. BMJ 323: 1417–1423PubMedCrossRef Hirsch L, Guess H (2001) Some clauses will hinder development of new drugs and vaccines. BMJ 323: 1417–1423PubMedCrossRef
55.
go back to reference Houtepen R, ter Meulen R (2000a) New types of solidarity in the European welfare state. Health Care Anal 8: 329–340PubMedCrossRef Houtepen R, ter Meulen R (2000a) New types of solidarity in the European welfare state. Health Care Anal 8: 329–340PubMedCrossRef
56.
go back to reference Houtepen R, ter Meulen R (2000b) The expectation(s) of solidarity: Matters of justice, responsibility and identity in the reconstruction of the health care system. Health Care Anal 8: 355–376PubMedCrossRef Houtepen R, ter Meulen R (2000b) The expectation(s) of solidarity: Matters of justice, responsibility and identity in the reconstruction of the health care system. Health Care Anal 8: 355–376PubMedCrossRef
57.
go back to reference HUGO Ethics Committee (2000) Statement on benefit sharing. At www.hugo-international.org/statement_on_benefit_sharing.htm HUGO Ethics Committee (2000) Statement on benefit sharing. At www.hugo-international.org/statement_on_benefit_sharing.htm
58.
go back to reference Human D, Fluss S (2001) The world medical association’s declaration of Helsinki: Historical and contemporary perspectives. At www.wma.net/e/ethicsunit/pdf/draft_historical_contemporary_perspectives.pdf Human D, Fluss S (2001) The world medical association’s declaration of Helsinki: Historical and contemporary perspectives. At www.wma.net/e/ethicsunit/pdf/draft_historical_contemporary_perspectives.pdf
59.
go back to reference Joint UN Program on HIV/AIDS (2003) AIDS Epidemic Update 2003, Geneva, UN, available at www.unaids.org Joint UN Program on HIV/AIDS (2003) AIDS Epidemic Update 2003, Geneva, UN, available at www.unaids.org
60.
61.
go back to reference Knoppers B (2005) Of genomics and public health: Building public ‘goods’?. CMAJ 173(10): 1185—1186.PubMed Knoppers B (2005) Of genomics and public health: Building public ‘goods’?. CMAJ 173(10): 1185—1186.PubMed
62.
63.
go back to reference Lolas F (2000) Ethics in international health research: The role of transnational organizations. At http: //bmj.bmjjournals.com/cgi/eletters/321/7264/777 Lolas F (2000) Ethics in international health research: The role of transnational organizations. At http: //bmj.bmjjournals.com/cgi/eletters/321/7264/777
64.
go back to reference Louw D (1997) Ubuntu: An African assessment of the religious other. At www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/ Afr/AfriLouw.htm Louw D (1997) Ubuntu: An African assessment of the religious other. At www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/ Afr/AfriLouw.htm
65.
go back to reference MacDonald C (2003) Patents and benefit-sharing as a challenge for corporate ethics. In: Knoppers B (ed) Populations and genetics: Legal and socio-ethical perspectives. Martinus Nijhoff, Boston, pp 505–523. MacDonald C (2003) Patents and benefit-sharing as a challenge for corporate ethics. In: Knoppers B (ed) Populations and genetics: Legal and socio-ethical perspectives. Martinus Nijhoff, Boston, pp 505–523.
66.
go back to reference Macer D, Su B (2004) Privacy versus public interest in developing human genetic databases. Eubios JAIB 14: 82–85 Macer D, Su B (2004) Privacy versus public interest in developing human genetic databases. Eubios JAIB 14: 82–85
67.
go back to reference Macer D (ed) (2004) Bioethics for informed citizens across cultures. Eubios Ethics Institute, NZ Macer D (ed) (2004) Bioethics for informed citizens across cultures. Eubios Ethics Institute, NZ
68.
go back to reference Macer D Love and the history of Chinese bioethics. At www.phil.pku.edu.cn/post/center/love%20and %20the%20history%20of%20chinese%20bioethics.html Macer D Love and the history of Chinese bioethics. At www.phil.pku.edu.cn/post/center/love%20and %20the%20history%20of%20chinese%20bioethics.html
69.
go back to reference Macklin R (2001) After Helsinki: Unresolved issues in international research. KIEJ 11: 17–36 Macklin R (2001) After Helsinki: Unresolved issues in international research. KIEJ 11: 17–36
71.
go back to reference Mayor F (1990) Statement at ‘Genetics, ethics and human values: Human genome mapping, genetic screening and gene therapy,’ 24th CIOMS Conference, Japan Mayor F (1990) Statement at ‘Genetics, ethics and human values: Human genome mapping, genetic screening and gene therapy,’ 24th CIOMS Conference, Japan
72.
go back to reference Mayor F (1994) Preface. In: Proceedings of the first session of the IBC. UNESCO, Paris Mayor F (1994) Preface. In: Proceedings of the first session of the IBC. UNESCO, Paris
73.
go back to reference McFaden A (1990) A call to personhood: A christian theory of the individual in social relationships. CUP, Cambridge McFaden A (1990) A call to personhood: A christian theory of the individual in social relationships. CUP, Cambridge
75.
76.
go back to reference McKibben W (2003) Enough. Bloomsbury, London McKibben W (2003) Enough. Bloomsbury, London
77.
go back to reference Morgan D (2002) Science, medicine and ethical change. In: Bainham A, et al (eds) Body lore and laws. Hart Publishing, Oxford, pp 329–342 Morgan D (2002) Science, medicine and ethical change. In: Bainham A, et al (eds) Body lore and laws. Hart Publishing, Oxford, pp 329–342
78.
go back to reference Morgan P, Lawton C (eds) (1996) Ethical issues in six religious traditions. EUP, Edinburgh Morgan P, Lawton C (eds) (1996) Ethical issues in six religious traditions. EUP, Edinburgh
79.
go back to reference Nuffield Council (2001) The ethics of clinical research in developing countries. NCB, London Nuffield Council (2001) The ethics of clinical research in developing countries. NCB, London
80.
go back to reference Nuffield Council (2002) The ethics of research related to healthcare in developing countries. NCB, London Nuffield Council (2002) The ethics of research related to healthcare in developing countries. NCB, London
81.
go back to reference Nuffield Council (2005) The ethics of research related to healthcare in developing countries. NCB, London Nuffield Council (2005) The ethics of research related to healthcare in developing countries. NCB, London
82.
go back to reference Onen C (2004) Medicine in resource-poor settings: Time for a paradigm shift? Clin Med 4: 355–360PubMed Onen C (2004) Medicine in resource-poor settings: Time for a paradigm shift? Clin Med 4: 355–360PubMed
83.
go back to reference Pettifor A (1996) Debt, the most potent form of slavery. Christian Aid Society, London Pettifor A (1996) Debt, the most potent form of slavery. Christian Aid Society, London
84.
go back to reference Polansky L (2000) The ramifications of population. ZPG Reporter 32: 5–13 Polansky L (2000) The ramifications of population. ZPG Reporter 32: 5–13
85.
go back to reference Pullman D, Latus A (2003) Reconciling social justice and economic opportunism: Regulating the newfoundland genome. In: Knoppers B (ed) Populations and genetics: Legal and socio-ethical perspectives. Martinus Nijhoff, Boston, pp 543–564 Pullman D, Latus A (2003) Reconciling social justice and economic opportunism: Regulating the newfoundland genome. In: Knoppers B (ed) Populations and genetics: Legal and socio-ethical perspectives. Martinus Nijhoff, Boston, pp 543–564
86.
go back to reference Resnik D (2004) The distribution of biomedical research resources and international justice. DWB 4: 42–57CrossRef Resnik D (2004) The distribution of biomedical research resources and international justice. DWB 4: 42–57CrossRef
87.
go back to reference Richards T (2002) Developed countries should not impose ethics on other countries. BMJ 325: 796CrossRef Richards T (2002) Developed countries should not impose ethics on other countries. BMJ 325: 796CrossRef
88.
go back to reference Schrecker T (2003) Benefit-sharing in the new genomic marketplace: Expanding the ethical frame of reference. In: Knoppers B (ed) Populations and genetics: Legal and socio-ethical perspectives. Martinus Nijhoff, Boston, pp 405–421 Schrecker T (2003) Benefit-sharing in the new genomic marketplace: Expanding the ethical frame of reference. In: Knoppers B (ed) Populations and genetics: Legal and socio-ethical perspectives. Martinus Nijhoff, Boston, pp 405–421
89.
go back to reference Shapiro K, Benatar S (2005) HIV prevention research and global inequality: Steps towards improved standards of care. J Med Ethics 31: 39–37PubMedCrossRef Shapiro K, Benatar S (2005) HIV prevention research and global inequality: Steps towards improved standards of care. J Med Ethics 31: 39–37PubMedCrossRef
90.
go back to reference Sitthi-amorn C et al (2002) The Asian voice in building equity in health for development—From the Asian forum for health research. Health Pol Plan 17: 213–217CrossRef Sitthi-amorn C et al (2002) The Asian voice in building equity in health for development—From the Asian forum for health research. Health Pol Plan 17: 213–217CrossRef
91.
go back to reference Steinbock B Rethinking the right to reproduce. At www.hsph.harvard.edu/organizations/healthnet/hupapers/reproright.html Steinbock B Rethinking the right to reproduce. At www.hsph.harvard.edu/organizations/healthnet/hupapers/reproright.html
92.
go back to reference Stenton G (2004) Biopiracy within the pharmaceutical industry: A stark illustration of how abusive, manipulative and perverse the patenting process can be towards countries of the south. EIPR 26(1): 17–26 Stenton G (2004) Biopiracy within the pharmaceutical industry: A stark illustration of how abusive, manipulative and perverse the patenting process can be towards countries of the south. EIPR 26(1): 17–26
93.
go back to reference Stuart S (2000) Species: Unprecedented extinction rate, and it’s increasing. IUCN Special Feature at www.iucn.org/info_and_news/press/species2000.html Stuart S (2000) Species: Unprecedented extinction rate, and it’s increasing. IUCN Special Feature at www.iucn.org/info_and_news/press/species2000.html
94.
go back to reference Suzuki Y (2003) Keynote address: International conference of drug regulatory authorities. At www.whqlibdoc.who.int/hq/2003/a79903_(chp3).pdf Suzuki Y (2003) Keynote address: International conference of drug regulatory authorities. At www.whqlibdoc.who.int/hq/2003/a79903_(chp3).pdf
95.
go back to reference ter Meulen R et al (2000) Final report: Solidarity and care in the European Union. At http: //europa.eu.int/ comm/research/biosociety/pdf/bmh4_ct8_3971_partb.pdf ter Meulen R et al (2000) Final report: Solidarity and care in the European Union. At http: //europa.eu.int/ comm/research/biosociety/pdf/bmh4_ct8_3971_partb.pdf
96.
go back to reference Tollman S (2001) What are the effects of the fifth revision of the declaration of Helsinki? Fair partnerships support ethical research. BMJ 323: 1417–1423PubMedCrossRef Tollman S (2001) What are the effects of the fifth revision of the declaration of Helsinki? Fair partnerships support ethical research. BMJ 323: 1417–1423PubMedCrossRef
97.
go back to reference UNESCO (2005) Explanatory memorandum on the elaboration of the preliminary draft declaration on universal norms on bioethics. UNESCO, Paris UNESCO (2005) Explanatory memorandum on the elaboration of the preliminary draft declaration on universal norms on bioethics. UNESCO, Paris
98.
go back to reference van Veen E (2005) Comments on the draft CIOMS international guidelines for ethical review of epidemiological studies. At www.medlaw.nl/documenten/comments.pdf van Veen E (2005) Comments on the draft CIOMS international guidelines for ethical review of epidemiological studies. At www.medlaw.nl/documenten/comments.pdf
99.
go back to reference Wallerstein I (1999) The end of the world as we know it: Social science for the twenty-first century. UMP, Minnesota Wallerstein I (1999) The end of the world as we know it: Social science for the twenty-first century. UMP, Minnesota
100.
go back to reference Weijer C, Anderson J (2001) The ethics wars: Disputes over international research. Hastings Centre Report 31, No. 3 Weijer C, Anderson J (2001) The ethics wars: Disputes over international research. Hastings Centre Report 31, No. 3
101.
go back to reference WHO (1999) Investing in health research and development. WHO Publications, Geneva WHO (1999) Investing in health research and development. WHO Publications, Geneva
102.
go back to reference WHO (2003) The world health report 2003. WHO Publications, Geneva WHO (2003) The world health report 2003. WHO Publications, Geneva
103.
go back to reference WHO (2005) World health report 2005. WHO Publications, Geneva WHO (2005) World health report 2005. WHO Publications, Geneva
104.
go back to reference WMA Working group report on the revision of paragraph 30 of the declaration of Helsinki. WG/DoH/Jan2004 WMA Working group report on the revision of paragraph 30 of the declaration of Helsinki. WG/DoH/Jan2004
105.
go back to reference Zadek S (1998) Balancing performance, ethics and accountability. J Bus Eth 17: 1421–1441CrossRef Zadek S (1998) Balancing performance, ethics and accountability. J Bus Eth 17: 1421–1441CrossRef
106.
go back to reference Zion D et al (2000) The declaration of Helsinki, CIOMS and the ethics of research on vulnerable populations. Nat Med 6: 615–617PubMedCrossRef Zion D et al (2000) The declaration of Helsinki, CIOMS and the ethics of research on vulnerable populations. Nat Med 6: 615–617PubMedCrossRef
Metadata
Title
Solidarity: A (New) Ethic for Global Health Policy
Author
Shawn H. E. Harmon
Publication date
01-12-2006
Published in
Health Care Analysis / Issue 4/2006
Print ISSN: 1065-3058
Electronic ISSN: 1573-3394
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-006-0030-8

Other articles of this Issue 4/2006

Health Care Analysis 4/2006 Go to the issue