Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 4/2012

01-12-2012 | Symposium

Heuristics and Life-Sustaining Treatments

Authors: Adam Feltz, Stephanie Samayoa

Published in: Journal of Bioethical Inquiry | Issue 4/2012

Login to get access

Abstract

Surrogates’ decisions to withhold or withdraw life-sustaining treatments (LSTs) are pervasive. However, the factors influencing surrogates’ decisions to initiate LSTs are relatively unknown. We present evidence from two experiments indicating that some surrogates’ decisions about when to initiate LSTs can be predictably manipulated. Factors that influence surrogate decisions about LSTs include the patient’s cognitive state, the patient’s age, the percentage of doctors not recommending the initiation of LSTs, the percentage of patients in similar situations not wanting LSTs, and default treatment settings. These results suggest that some people may use heuristics when making these important life-and-death decisions. These findings may have important moral implications for improving surrogate decisions about LSTs and reconsidering paternalism.
Footnotes
1
Many theorists (e.g., experimental philosophers) have been using empirical methods to help shed light on philosophically important issues. These issues have included ethics (e.g., Nadelhoffer and Feltz 2008), epistemology (e.g., Feltz and Zarpentine 2010; Weinberg, Nichols, and Stich 2001), philosophy of mind (e.g., Cokely and Feltz 2009; Feltz, Cokely, and Nadelhoffer 2009), and applied ethics (Feltz and Cokely in press; Cokely and Feltz in press; Allhoff 2003, 2005).
 
2
All of our studies followed this same procedure and the participants had the same basic demographics. Since these demographics were not involved in predictions in our studies, we do not report them in subsequent studies.
 
3
Following a significant result from a MANOVA with ANOVAs is a tested practice. See Hummel and Sligo (1971) and Rencher and Scott (1990).
 
4
One worry with Experiment 1b and 1c is that the prompts indicate doctors’ recommendations against and other patients’ preference against treatment. This may make the prompts particularly difficult to understand. While failures on the comprehension question were consistent with the other studies in Experiment 1, it still could be that many people did not truly understand the nature of the question. If that is the case, then we actually underestimate the effects, since the confusion would reduce the true effect.
 
5
For example, because people have a tendency to stick with defaults, that bias may lead to better decisions for things such as organ donation (Johnson and Goldstein 2003). However, these biases can also lead to worse decisions, such as sticking with some default retirement plans that have lower overall expected value (Choi et al. 2002).
 
Literature
go back to reference Allen-Burge, R., and W.E. Haley. 1997. Individual differences and surrogate medical decisions: Differing preferences for life-sustaining treatments. Aging & Mental Health 1(2): 121–131.CrossRef Allen-Burge, R., and W.E. Haley. 1997. Individual differences and surrogate medical decisions: Differing preferences for life-sustaining treatments. Aging & Mental Health 1(2): 121–131.CrossRef
go back to reference Allhoff, F. 2003. Terrorism and torture. International Journal of Applied Philosophy 17(1): 105–118. Allhoff, F. 2003. Terrorism and torture. International Journal of Applied Philosophy 17(1): 105–118.
go back to reference Allhoff, F. 2005. A defense of torture: Separation of cases, ticking time-bombs, and moral justification. International Journal of Applied Philosophy 19(2): 243–264. Allhoff, F. 2005. A defense of torture: Separation of cases, ticking time-bombs, and moral justification. International Journal of Applied Philosophy 19(2): 243–264.
go back to reference American Medical Association. 2010. Code of medical ethics. Chicago: American Medical Association. American Medical Association. 2010. Code of medical ethics. Chicago: American Medical Association.
go back to reference Berg, N., and G. Gigerenzer. 2007. Psychology implies paternalism? Bounded rationality may reduce the rationale to regulate risk-taking. Social Choice and Welfare 28(2): 337–359.CrossRef Berg, N., and G. Gigerenzer. 2007. Psychology implies paternalism? Bounded rationality may reduce the rationale to regulate risk-taking. Social Choice and Welfare 28(2): 337–359.CrossRef
go back to reference Braun, U.K., and L.B. McCullough. 2011. Preventing life-sustaining treatment by default. Annals of Family Medicine 9(3): 250–256.PubMedCrossRef Braun, U.K., and L.B. McCullough. 2011. Preventing life-sustaining treatment by default. Annals of Family Medicine 9(3): 250–256.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Buhrmester, M., T. Kwang, and S.D. Gosling. 2011. Amazon’s Mechanical Turk: A new source of inexpensive, yet high-quality, data? Perspectives on Psychological Science 6(1): 3–5.CrossRef Buhrmester, M., T. Kwang, and S.D. Gosling. 2011. Amazon’s Mechanical Turk: A new source of inexpensive, yet high-quality, data? Perspectives on Psychological Science 6(1): 3–5.CrossRef
go back to reference Choi, J.J., D. Laibson, B.C. Madrain, and A. Metrick. 2002. Defined contribution pensions: Plan rules, participants decisions, and the path of least resistance. In Tax and the economy, ed. J. Poterba, 67–113. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Choi, J.J., D. Laibson, B.C. Madrain, and A. Metrick. 2002. Defined contribution pensions: Plan rules, participants decisions, and the path of least resistance. In Tax and the economy, ed. J. Poterba, 67–113. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
go back to reference Cokely, E.T., and A. Feltz. 2009. Individual differences, judgment biases, and theory-of-mind: Deconstructing the intentional action side effect asymmetry. Journal of Research in Personality 43(1): 18–24.CrossRef Cokely, E.T., and A. Feltz. 2009. Individual differences, judgment biases, and theory-of-mind: Deconstructing the intentional action side effect asymmetry. Journal of Research in Personality 43(1): 18–24.CrossRef
go back to reference Cokely, E.T., and A. Feltz. 2010. Adaptive diversity and misbelief. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32(6): 516.CrossRef Cokely, E.T., and A. Feltz. 2010. Adaptive diversity and misbelief. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32(6): 516.CrossRef
go back to reference Cokely, E.T., and A. Feltz. In press. Virtue in business: Morally better, praiseworthy, trustworthy, and more satisfying. Journal of Organizational Moral Psychology. Cokely, E.T., and A. Feltz. In press. Virtue in business: Morally better, praiseworthy, trustworthy, and more satisfying. Journal of Organizational Moral Psychology.
go back to reference Cokely, E.T., and C.M. Kelley. 2009. Cognitive abilities and superior decision making under risk: A protocol analysis and process model evaluation. Judgment and Decision Making 4(1): 20–33. Cokely, E.T., and C.M. Kelley. 2009. Cognitive abilities and superior decision making under risk: A protocol analysis and process model evaluation. Judgment and Decision Making 4(1): 20–33.
go back to reference Cokely, E.T., C.M. Kelley, and A.L. Gilchrist. 2006. Sources of individual differences in working memory: Contributions of strategy to capacity. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 13(6): 991–997.PubMedCrossRef Cokely, E.T., C.M. Kelley, and A.L. Gilchrist. 2006. Sources of individual differences in working memory: Contributions of strategy to capacity. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 13(6): 991–997.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Deutsch, M., and H.B. Gerard. 1955. A study of normative and informational social influences upon individual judgment. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 51(3): 629–636.CrossRef Deutsch, M., and H.B. Gerard. 1955. A study of normative and informational social influences upon individual judgment. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 51(3): 629–636.CrossRef
go back to reference Ditto, P.H., J.H. Danks, W.D. Smucker, et al. 2001. Advance directives as acts of communication: A randomized controlled trial. Archives of Internal Medicine 161(3): 421–430.PubMedCrossRef Ditto, P.H., J.H. Danks, W.D. Smucker, et al. 2001. Advance directives as acts of communication: A randomized controlled trial. Archives of Internal Medicine 161(3): 421–430.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Fagerlin, A., P.H. Ditto, J.H. Danks, R.M. Houts, and W.D. Smucker. 2001. Projection in surrogate decisions about life-sustaining medical treatments. Health Psychology 20(3): 166–175.PubMedCrossRef Fagerlin, A., P.H. Ditto, J.H. Danks, R.M. Houts, and W.D. Smucker. 2001. Projection in surrogate decisions about life-sustaining medical treatments. Health Psychology 20(3): 166–175.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Feltz, A., and E.T. Cokely. In press. The philosophical personality argument. Philosophical Studies. Feltz, A., and E.T. Cokely. In press. The philosophical personality argument. Philosophical Studies.
go back to reference Feltz, A., E.T. Cokely, and T. Nadelhoffer. 2009. Natural compatibilism versus natural incompatibilism: Back to the drawing board. Mind & Language 24(1): 1–23.CrossRef Feltz, A., E.T. Cokely, and T. Nadelhoffer. 2009. Natural compatibilism versus natural incompatibilism: Back to the drawing board. Mind & Language 24(1): 1–23.CrossRef
go back to reference Feltz, A., and C. Zarpentine. 2010. Do you know more when it matters less? Philosophical Psychology 23(5): 683–706.CrossRef Feltz, A., and C. Zarpentine. 2010. Do you know more when it matters less? Philosophical Psychology 23(5): 683–706.CrossRef
go back to reference Gehrig, T., W. Güth, R. Levínský, and V. Popova. 2008. Do investors optimize, follow heuristics, or listen to experts? Jena Economic Research Papers 86(2): 1–43. Gehrig, T., W. Güth, R. Levínský, and V. Popova. 2008. Do investors optimize, follow heuristics, or listen to experts? Jena Economic Research Papers 86(2): 1–43.
go back to reference Gerard, H., R. Wilhelmy, and E. Conolley. 1968. Conformity and group size. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 8: 79–82.PubMedCrossRef Gerard, H., R. Wilhelmy, and E. Conolley. 1968. Conformity and group size. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 8: 79–82.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Gigerenzer, G. 2000. Adaptive thinking: Rationality in the real world. New York: Oxford University Press. Gigerenzer, G. 2000. Adaptive thinking: Rationality in the real world. New York: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Gigerenzer, G., P. Todd, and The ABC Group. 1999. Simple heuristics that make us smart. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gigerenzer, G., P. Todd, and The ABC Group. 1999. Simple heuristics that make us smart. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Glaeser, E.L. 2006. Paternalism and psychology. The University of Chicago Law Review 73: 133–156. Glaeser, E.L. 2006. Paternalism and psychology. The University of Chicago Law Review 73: 133–156.
go back to reference Goldberg, S.C. 1954. The situational determinants of conformity to social norms. The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 49(3): 325–329.CrossRef Goldberg, S.C. 1954. The situational determinants of conformity to social norms. The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 49(3): 325–329.CrossRef
go back to reference Halpern, S.D., P.A. Ubel, and D.A. Asch. 2007. Harnessing the power of default options to improve health care. The New England Journal of Medicine 357(13): 1340–1344.PubMedCrossRef Halpern, S.D., P.A. Ubel, and D.A. Asch. 2007. Harnessing the power of default options to improve health care. The New England Journal of Medicine 357(13): 1340–1344.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Hammel, M.B., J.M. Teno, L. Goldman, et al. 1999. Patient age and decisions to withhold life-sustaining treatments from seriously ill, hospitalized adults. SUPPORT Investigators. Study to Understand Prognoses and Preferences for Outcomes and Risks of Treatment. Annals of Internal Medicine 130(2): 116–125. Hammel, M.B., J.M. Teno, L. Goldman, et al. 1999. Patient age and decisions to withhold life-sustaining treatments from seriously ill, hospitalized adults. SUPPORT Investigators. Study to Understand Prognoses and Preferences for Outcomes and Risks of Treatment. Annals of Internal Medicine 130(2): 116–125.
go back to reference Hummel, T.J., and J.R. Sligo. 1971. Empirical comparison of univariate and multivariate analysis of variance procedures. Psychological Bulletin 76(1): 49–57.CrossRef Hummel, T.J., and J.R. Sligo. 1971. Empirical comparison of univariate and multivariate analysis of variance procedures. Psychological Bulletin 76(1): 49–57.CrossRef
go back to reference Jansen, L.A., and S. Wall. 2009. Paternalism and fairness in clinical research. Bioethics 23(3): 172–182.PubMedCrossRef Jansen, L.A., and S. Wall. 2009. Paternalism and fairness in clinical research. Bioethics 23(3): 172–182.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Korobkin, R. 2009. Libertarian welfarism. California Law Review 97(6): 1651–1685. Korobkin, R. 2009. Libertarian welfarism. California Law Review 97(6): 1651–1685.
go back to reference Kuczewski, M.G. 1999. Commentary: Narrative views of personal identity and substituted judgment in surrogate decision making. The Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 27(1): 32–36.CrossRef Kuczewski, M.G. 1999. Commentary: Narrative views of personal identity and substituted judgment in surrogate decision making. The Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 27(1): 32–36.CrossRef
go back to reference Lascu, D.-N., W.O. Bearden, and R.L. Rose. 1995. Norm extremity and interpersonal influences on consumer conformity. Journal of Business Research 32(3): 201–212.CrossRef Lascu, D.-N., W.O. Bearden, and R.L. Rose. 1995. Norm extremity and interpersonal influences on consumer conformity. Journal of Business Research 32(3): 201–212.CrossRef
go back to reference Marks, M.A.Z., and H.R. Arkes. 2008. Patient and surrogate disagreement in end-of-life decisions: Can surrogates accurately predict patients’ preferences? Medical Decision Making 28(4): 524–531.PubMedCrossRef Marks, M.A.Z., and H.R. Arkes. 2008. Patient and surrogate disagreement in end-of-life decisions: Can surrogates accurately predict patients’ preferences? Medical Decision Making 28(4): 524–531.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Martin, R., A. Gardikiotis, and M. Hewstone. 2002. Levels of consensus and majority and minority influence. European Journal of Social Psychology 32(5): 645–665.CrossRef Martin, R., A. Gardikiotis, and M. Hewstone. 2002. Levels of consensus and majority and minority influence. European Journal of Social Psychology 32(5): 645–665.CrossRef
go back to reference McKenzie, C.R.M., M.J. Liersch, and S.R. Finkelstein. 2006. Recommendations implicit in policy defaults. Psychological Science 17(5): 414–420.PubMedCrossRef McKenzie, C.R.M., M.J. Liersch, and S.R. Finkelstein. 2006. Recommendations implicit in policy defaults. Psychological Science 17(5): 414–420.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Ménard, J.-F. 2010. A “nudge” for public health ethics: Libertarian paternalism as a framework for ethical analysis of public health interventions? Public Health Ethics 3(3): 229–238.CrossRef Ménard, J.-F. 2010. A “nudge” for public health ethics: Libertarian paternalism as a framework for ethical analysis of public health interventions? Public Health Ethics 3(3): 229–238.CrossRef
go back to reference Nadelhoffer, T., and A. Feltz. 2008. The actor-observer bias and moral intuitions: Adding fuel to Sinnott-Armstrong’s fire. Neuroethics 1(2): 133–144.CrossRef Nadelhoffer, T., and A. Feltz. 2008. The actor-observer bias and moral intuitions: Adding fuel to Sinnott-Armstrong’s fire. Neuroethics 1(2): 133–144.CrossRef
go back to reference Nordholm, L.A. 1975. Effects of group size and stimulus ambiguity on conformity. The Journal of Social Psychology 97(1): 123–130.CrossRef Nordholm, L.A. 1975. Effects of group size and stimulus ambiguity on conformity. The Journal of Social Psychology 97(1): 123–130.CrossRef
go back to reference Pousset, G., J. Bilsen, J. De Wilde, L. Deliens, and F. Mortier. 2009. Attitudes of Flemish secondary school students towards euthanasia and other end-of-life decisions in minors. Child: Care, Health and Development 35(3): 349–356.CrossRef Pousset, G., J. Bilsen, J. De Wilde, L. Deliens, and F. Mortier. 2009. Attitudes of Flemish secondary school students towards euthanasia and other end-of-life decisions in minors. Child: Care, Health and Development 35(3): 349–356.CrossRef
go back to reference Prendergast, T.J., M.T. Claessens, and J.M. Luce. 1998. A national survey of end-of-life care for critically ill patients. American Journal of Respiratory and Critical Care Medicine 158(4): 1163–1167.PubMed Prendergast, T.J., M.T. Claessens, and J.M. Luce. 1998. A national survey of end-of-life care for critically ill patients. American Journal of Respiratory and Critical Care Medicine 158(4): 1163–1167.PubMed
go back to reference Rachlinski, J.J. 2006. Cognitive errors, individual differences, and paternalism. The University of Chicago Law Review 73: 207–229. Rachlinski, J.J. 2006. Cognitive errors, individual differences, and paternalism. The University of Chicago Law Review 73: 207–229.
go back to reference Rencher, A.C., and D.T. Scott. 1990. Assessing the contribution of individual variables following rejection of a multivariate hypothesis. Communication in Statistics: Simulation and Computation 19(2): 535–553.CrossRef Rencher, A.C., and D.T. Scott. 1990. Assessing the contribution of individual variables following rejection of a multivariate hypothesis. Communication in Statistics: Simulation and Computation 19(2): 535–553.CrossRef
go back to reference Rid, A., and D. Wendler. 2010. Can we improve treatment decision-making for incapacitated patients? The Hastings Center Report 40(5): 36–45.PubMedCrossRef Rid, A., and D. Wendler. 2010. Can we improve treatment decision-making for incapacitated patients? The Hastings Center Report 40(5): 36–45.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Sadrieh, A., W. Güth, P. Hammerstein, et al. 2002. Group report: Is there evidence for an adaptive toolbox? In Bounded rationality: The adaptive toolbox, ed. G. Gigerenzer and R. Selten, 83–102. Cambridge: MIT Press. Sadrieh, A., W. Güth, P. Hammerstein, et al. 2002. Group report: Is there evidence for an adaptive toolbox? In Bounded rationality: The adaptive toolbox, ed. G. Gigerenzer and R. Selten, 83–102. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Shalowitz, D.I., E. Garrett-Mayer, and D. Wendler. 2006. The accuracy of surrogate decision makers: A systematic review. Archives of Internal Medicine 166(5): 493–497.PubMedCrossRef Shalowitz, D.I., E. Garrett-Mayer, and D. Wendler. 2006. The accuracy of surrogate decision makers: A systematic review. Archives of Internal Medicine 166(5): 493–497.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Sharman, S.J., M. Garry, J.A. Jacobson, E.F. Loftus, and P.H. Ditto. 2008. False memories for end-of-life decisions. Health Psychology 27(2): 291–296.PubMedCrossRef Sharman, S.J., M. Garry, J.A. Jacobson, E.F. Loftus, and P.H. Ditto. 2008. False memories for end-of-life decisions. Health Psychology 27(2): 291–296.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Sulmasy, D.P., P.B. Terry, C.S. Weisman, et al. 1998. The accuracy of substituted judgments in patients with terminal diagnoses. Annals of Internal Medicine 128(8): 621–629.PubMed Sulmasy, D.P., P.B. Terry, C.S. Weisman, et al. 1998. The accuracy of substituted judgments in patients with terminal diagnoses. Annals of Internal Medicine 128(8): 621–629.PubMed
go back to reference Sunstein, C.R., and R.H. Thaler. 2003. Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron. The University of Chicago Law Review 70: 1159–1202.CrossRef Sunstein, C.R., and R.H. Thaler. 2003. Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron. The University of Chicago Law Review 70: 1159–1202.CrossRef
go back to reference Teno, J.M., H.L. Nelson, and J. Lynn. 1994. Advance care planning: Priorities for ethical and empirical research. The Hastings Center Report 24(6): S32–S36.PubMedCrossRef Teno, J.M., H.L. Nelson, and J. Lynn. 1994. Advance care planning: Priorities for ethical and empirical research. The Hastings Center Report 24(6): S32–S36.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Thaler, R.H., and C.R. Sunstein. 2008. Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New Haven: Yale University Press. Thaler, R.H., and C.R. Sunstein. 2008. Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New Haven: Yale University Press.
go back to reference Todd, P.M., and G. Gigerenzer. 2007. Ecological rationality. Current Directions in Psychological Science 16(3): 167–171.CrossRef Todd, P.M., and G. Gigerenzer. 2007. Ecological rationality. Current Directions in Psychological Science 16(3): 167–171.CrossRef
go back to reference Torke, A.M., G.A. Sachs, P.R. Helft, et al. 2011. Timing of do-not-resuscitate orders for hospitalized older adults who require a surrogate decision-maker. Journal of American Geriatrics Society 59(7): 1326–1331.CrossRef Torke, A.M., G.A. Sachs, P.R. Helft, et al. 2011. Timing of do-not-resuscitate orders for hospitalized older adults who require a surrogate decision-maker. Journal of American Geriatrics Society 59(7): 1326–1331.CrossRef
go back to reference Torke, A.M., M. Siegler, A. Abalos, R.M. Moloney, and G.C. Alexander. 2009. Physicians’ experience with surrogate decision making for hospitalized adults. Journal of General Internal Medicine 24(9): 1023–1028.PubMedCrossRef Torke, A.M., M. Siegler, A. Abalos, R.M. Moloney, and G.C. Alexander. 2009. Physicians’ experience with surrogate decision making for hospitalized adults. Journal of General Internal Medicine 24(9): 1023–1028.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Trout, J.D. 2005. Paternalism and cognitive bias. Law and Philosophy 24(4): 393–434.CrossRef Trout, J.D. 2005. Paternalism and cognitive bias. Law and Philosophy 24(4): 393–434.CrossRef
go back to reference Uhlmann, R.F., R.A. Pearlman, and K.C. Cain. 1988. Physicians’ and spouses’ predictions of elderly patients’ resuscitation preferences. Journal of Gerontology 43(5): M115–M121.PubMedCrossRef Uhlmann, R.F., R.A. Pearlman, and K.C. Cain. 1988. Physicians’ and spouses’ predictions of elderly patients’ resuscitation preferences. Journal of Gerontology 43(5): M115–M121.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Weinberg, J.M., S. Nichols, and S. Stich. 2001. Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics 29(1–2): 429–460. Weinberg, J.M., S. Nichols, and S. Stich. 2001. Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics 29(1–2): 429–460.
go back to reference Williams, N., C. Dunford, A. Knowles, and J. Warner. 2007. Public attitudes to life-sustaining treatments and euthanasia in dementia. International Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry 22(12): 1229–1234.PubMedCrossRef Williams, N., C. Dunford, A. Knowles, and J. Warner. 2007. Public attitudes to life-sustaining treatments and euthanasia in dementia. International Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry 22(12): 1229–1234.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Wilson, K.G., H.M. Pinocchio, C.J. McPherson, et al. 2007. Desire for euthanasia or physician-assisted suicide in palliative cancer care. Health Psychology 26(3): 314–323.PubMedCrossRef Wilson, K.G., H.M. Pinocchio, C.J. McPherson, et al. 2007. Desire for euthanasia or physician-assisted suicide in palliative cancer care. Health Psychology 26(3): 314–323.PubMedCrossRef
Metadata
Title
Heuristics and Life-Sustaining Treatments
Authors
Adam Feltz
Stephanie Samayoa
Publication date
01-12-2012
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Journal of Bioethical Inquiry / Issue 4/2012
Print ISSN: 1176-7529
Electronic ISSN: 1872-4353
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-012-9396-5

Other articles of this Issue 4/2012

Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 4/2012 Go to the issue

Book Review

Jewish Eugenics