Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 1/2016

01-03-2016 | Scientific Contribution

Heidegger, ontological death, and the healing professions

Author: Kevin A. Aho

Published in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy | Issue 1/2016

Login to get access

Abstract

In Being and Time, Martin Heidegger introduces a unique interpretation of death as a kind of world-collapse or breakdown of meaning that strips away our ability to understand and make sense of who we are. This is an ‘ontological death’ in the sense that we cannot be anything because the intelligible world that we draw on to fashion our identities and sustain our sense of self has lost all significance. On this account, death is not only an event that we can physiologically live through; it can happen numerous times throughout the finite span of our lives. This paper draws on Arthur Frank’s (At the will of the body: reflections on illness. Houghton, Boston, 1991) narrative of critical illness to concretize the experience of ‘ontological death’ and illuminate the unique challenges it poses for health care professionals. I turn to Heidegger’s conception of ‘resoluteness’ (Entschlossenheit) to address these challenges, arguing for the need of health care professionals to help establish a discursive context whereby the critically ill can begin to meaningfully express and interpret their experience of self-loss in a way that acknowledges the structural vulnerability of their own identities and is flexible enough to let go of those that have lost their significance or viability.
Footnotes
1
There has been a great deal of discussion on the meaning of death in Heidegger’s thought in recent years. Some of the more influential interpretations can be found in Blattner (1994, 2006), Carman (2003), Guignon (1983, 2011), Haugland (2000), Hoffman (1993), Mulhall (2005), Thomson (2013), and White (2005). For a concise overview of leading Anglophone interpretations of Heidegger on death, see Dreyfus (2005).
 
2
This interpretation is supported by the fact that Heidegger’s discussion of the myriad ways in which we cover over and evade the ‘mineness’ of death is clearly influenced by Leo Tolstoy’s The Death of Ivan Ilych, a story that provides what is perhaps the definitive existentialist account of death (e.g. Heidegger 1927/1962, 254n12).
 
3
For a comprehensive account of why Heidegger avoids an analysis of the body in Being and Time, see Aho (2009).
 
4
For a rich account of the relation between fear and anxiety as it pertains to being-towards-death, see Thomson (2013).
 
5
Understanding world-collapse as a structure of Dasein helps explain what Heidegger means when he says, “The ‘nothing’ exhibits itself as that in the face of which one has anxiety, this means that being-in-world [or Dasein] itself is that in the face of which anxiety is anxious” (1927/1962, 187).
 
6
This is why Heidegger can say that ontological death is both ‘certain’ and ‘indefinite’. The public world “covers up what is peculiar in death’s certainty—that it is possible at any moment. Along with the certainty of death goes the indefiniteness of its ‘when’.” (1927/1962, 258) Death is certain in the sense that the self-interpretive activity of being human is structured in a way that is always vulnerable to collapse; but it is indefinite in the sense that we have no idea if and when this collapse will happen.
 
7
I am indebted to Charles Guignon for pointing this out. For more on the ambiguous etymology of Entschlossenheit, see Stambaugh (1987).
 
8
Heidegger explains, “The rarity of the phenomenon [of anxiety] is an index that Dasein… remains concealed from itself… because of the way in which things have been publicly interpreted by ‘the Anyone’” (1927/1962, 190).
 
9
Heidegger also mentions that “anxiety is often conditioned by ‘physiological factors’” (1927/1962, 190), which may suggest that those individuals equipped with an especially strong or resilient nervous system may be shielded from ever experiencing their own structural vulnerability.
 
10
The data in Charmaz’s study comes from “73 in-depth interviews with 57 chronically ill persons in northern California who have various diagnoses such as cardiovascular disease, diabetes, cancer, multiple sclerosis, lupus erythematosus and so forth” (1983, 171).
 
11
Frank writes, for instance, of the ways in which his nurses focused only on his physical suffering, how they refused to use the word ‘cancer’ around him, referring to him merely as the “seminoma in [room] 53,” and how they frequently cited other patients as being much “much worse off” than he was (1991, 100–101). Indeed, the only way he could get his surgeon to talk meaningfully to him about his experience of suffering was by refusing to sign the consent form.
 
12
This does not mean Heidegger is promoting a kind of postmodern dismissal of selfhood. The interpretive activity of Dasein provides for a relatively cohesive and unified sense of self as a whole. The problem arises when I confuse the cohesiveness of my narrative identity with permanence and become convinced that the interpretation I have of myself is the ‘real me’.
 
13
It is important to note that Heidegger rejects the existentialist (e.g. Sartre’s) conception of the radical or absolute subject who creates her identity ex nihilo. This is because the meaning and significance of any identity Dasein commits to in the wake of ‘ontological death’ has already been established and interpreted by the public world. In short, Dasein, whether authentic or inauthentic, is never ‘world-less’. This is why Heidegger says, “Resoluteness, as authentic being-one’s-self, does not detach Dasein from its world, nor does it isolate it so that it becomes a free-floating ‘I’. And how should it, when resoluteness as authentic disclosedness, is authentically nothing else than being-in-the-world? Resoluteness brings the self right into its current concernful being-alongside what is ready-to-hand, and pushes it in solicitous being with others” (1927/1962, 298).
 
Literature
go back to reference Aho, K. 2009. Heidegger’s neglect of the body. Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Aho, K. 2009. Heidegger’s neglect of the body. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
go back to reference Aho, K. 2014. Depression and embodiment: Phenomenological reflections on motility, affectivity, and transcendence. Medicine, Healthcare, and Philosophy 16(4): 751–759.CrossRef Aho, K. 2014. Depression and embodiment: Phenomenological reflections on motility, affectivity, and transcendence. Medicine, Healthcare, and Philosophy 16(4): 751–759.CrossRef
go back to reference Blattner, W. 1994. The concept of death in Being and Time. Man and World 27: 49–70.CrossRef Blattner, W. 1994. The concept of death in Being and Time. Man and World 27: 49–70.CrossRef
go back to reference Blattner, W. 2009. Heidegger’s Being and Time. New York, London: Continuum. Blattner, W. 2009. Heidegger’s Being and Time. New York, London: Continuum.
go back to reference Carman, T. 2003. Heidegger’s analytic: Interpretation, discourse, and authenticity in Being and Time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Carman, T. 2003. Heidegger’s analytic: Interpretation, discourse, and authenticity in Being and Time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Chamaz, K. 1983. Loss of self: A fundamental form of suffering in the chronically ill. Sociology of Health & Illness 5(2): 168–195.CrossRef Chamaz, K. 1983. Loss of self: A fundamental form of suffering in the chronically ill. Sociology of Health & Illness 5(2): 168–195.CrossRef
go back to reference Caputo, J. 1994. Sorge and kardia: The hermeneutics of factical life and the categories of the heart. In Reading Heidegger from the start: Essays in his earliest thought, ed. T. Kisiel, and J. van Buren, 327–344. Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Caputo, J. 1994. Sorge and kardia: The hermeneutics of factical life and the categories of the heart. In Reading Heidegger from the start: Essays in his earliest thought, ed. T. Kisiel, and J. van Buren, 327–344. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
go back to reference Dreyfus, H. 2005. Forward to Carol White’s time and death: Heidegger’s analysis of finitude, ix–xxxvi. London: Ashgate. Dreyfus, H. 2005. Forward to Carol White’s time and death: Heidegger’s analysis of finitude, ix–xxxvi. London: Ashgate.
go back to reference Frank, A. 1991. At the will of the body: Reflections on illness. Boston, New York: Houghton Mifflin Company. Frank, A. 1991. At the will of the body: Reflections on illness. Boston, New York: Houghton Mifflin Company.
go back to reference Guignon, C. 1983. Heidegger and the problem of knowledge. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Press. Guignon, C. 1983. Heidegger and the problem of knowledge. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Press.
go back to reference Guignon, C. 2004. On being authentic. London: Routledge. Guignon, C. 2004. On being authentic. London: Routledge.
go back to reference Guignon, C. 2011. Heidegger and Kierkegaard on death: Existentiell and the existential. In Kierkegaard and death, ed. P. Stokes, and A. Buben, 184–203. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Guignon, C. 2011. Heidegger and Kierkegaard on death: Existentiell and the existential. In Kierkegaard and death, ed. P. Stokes, and A. Buben, 184–203. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
go back to reference Haugland, J. 2000. Truth and finitude: Heidegger’s transcendental existentialism. In Heidegger, authenticity, and modernity: Essays in honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus, ed. M. Wrathall, and J. Malpas, 43–78. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Haugland, J. 2000. Truth and finitude: Heidegger’s transcendental existentialism. In Heidegger, authenticity, and modernity: Essays in honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus, ed. M. Wrathall, and J. Malpas, 43–78. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Heidegger, M. 1927/1962. Being and Time. Trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. New York: Harper and Row. All references are to the German pagination. Heidegger, M. 1927/1962. Being and Time. Trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. New York: Harper and Row. All references are to the German pagination.
go back to reference Heidegger, M. 1971. Poetry, language, thought, trans. A. Hofstadter. New York: Harper and Row. Heidegger, M. 1971. Poetry, language, thought, trans. A. Hofstadter. New York: Harper and Row.
go back to reference Heidegger, M. 1979. Nietzsche volume I: The will to power as art. Trans. D. F. Krell. New York: HarperCollins. Heidegger, M. 1979. Nietzsche volume I: The will to power as art. Trans. D. F. Krell. New York: HarperCollins.
go back to reference Heidegger, M. 1982. Basic problems of phenomenology. Trans. A. Hofstadter. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Heidegger, M. 1982. Basic problems of phenomenology. Trans. A. Hofstadter. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
go back to reference Heidegger, M. 1984. The metaphysical foundations of logic. Trans. M. Heim. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Heidegger, M. 1984. The metaphysical foundations of logic. Trans. M. Heim. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
go back to reference Heidegger, M. 1995. Fundamental concepts of metaphysics: World, finitude, solitude. Trans. W. McNeill and N. Walker. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Heidegger, M. 1995. Fundamental concepts of metaphysics: World, finitude, solitude. Trans. W. McNeill and N. Walker. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
go back to reference Hoffman, P. 1993. Death, time, history: Division II of Being and Time. In The Cambridge companion to Heidegger, ed. Charles Guignon, 195–214. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Hoffman, P. 1993. Death, time, history: Division II of Being and Time. In The Cambridge companion to Heidegger, ed. Charles Guignon, 195–214. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Karp, D. 1996. Speaking of sadness: Depression, disconnection, and the meanings of illness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Karp, D. 1996. Speaking of sadness: Depression, disconnection, and the meanings of illness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Mulhall, S. 2005. Human mortality: Heidegger on how to portray the impossible possibility of Dasein. In A companion to Heidegger, ed. H. Dreyfus, and M. Wrathall, 297–310. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRef Mulhall, S. 2005. Human mortality: Heidegger on how to portray the impossible possibility of Dasein. In A companion to Heidegger, ed. H. Dreyfus, and M. Wrathall, 297–310. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRef
go back to reference Ricoeur, P. 1981. Hermeneutics and the human sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ricoeur, P. 1981. Hermeneutics and the human sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Sartre, J.-P. 1953/1956. Being and nothingness: An essay in phenomenological ontology. Trans. H. Barnes. Secaucus, NJ: The Citadel Press. Sartre, J.-P. 1953/1956. Being and nothingness: An essay in phenomenological ontology. Trans. H. Barnes. Secaucus, NJ: The Citadel Press.
go back to reference Schultz, D., and L. Flasher. 2011. Charles Taylor, phronesis, and medicine: Ethics and interpretation in illness narrative. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 36: 394–409.CrossRef Schultz, D., and L. Flasher. 2011. Charles Taylor, phronesis, and medicine: Ethics and interpretation in illness narrative. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 36: 394–409.CrossRef
go back to reference Stambaugh, J. 1987. Heidegger, Taoism, and metaphysics. In Heidegger and Asian thought, ed. G. Parkes, 79–92. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. Stambaugh, J. 1987. Heidegger, Taoism, and metaphysics. In Heidegger and Asian thought, ed. G. Parkes, 79–92. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.
go back to reference Svenaeus, F. 2011. Illness as unhomelike being-in-the-world: Heidegger and the phenomenology of medicine. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 14(3): 333–343.CrossRef Svenaeus, F. 2011. Illness as unhomelike being-in-the-world: Heidegger and the phenomenology of medicine. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 14(3): 333–343.CrossRef
go back to reference Taylor, C. 1985. Human agency and language: Philosophical papers. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Taylor, C. 1985. Human agency and language: Philosophical papers. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Thomson, I. 2013. Death and demise in Being and Time. In The Cambridge companion to Heidegger’s Being and Time, ed. Mark Wrathall, 260–290. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Thomson, I. 2013. Death and demise in Being and Time. In The Cambridge companion to Heidegger’s Being and Time, ed. Mark Wrathall, 260–290. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Tolstoy, L. 1994. My confession, my religion. Trans. I. Hapgood. Midland, MI: Avensblume Press. Tolstoy, L. 1994. My confession, my religion. Trans. I. Hapgood. Midland, MI: Avensblume Press.
go back to reference White, C. 2005. Time and death: Heidegger’s analysis of finitude. London: Ashgate. White, C. 2005. Time and death: Heidegger’s analysis of finitude. London: Ashgate.
Metadata
Title
Heidegger, ontological death, and the healing professions
Author
Kevin A. Aho
Publication date
01-03-2016
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy / Issue 1/2016
Print ISSN: 1386-7423
Electronic ISSN: 1572-8633
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-015-9639-4

Other articles of this Issue 1/2016

Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 1/2016 Go to the issue