Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Health Care Analysis 2/2017

01-06-2017 | Original Article

Medical Need: Evaluating a Conceptual Critique of Universal Health Coverage

Author: Lynette Reid

Published in: Health Care Analysis | Issue 2/2017

Login to get access

Abstract

Some argue that the concept of medical need is inadequate to inform the design of a universal health care system—particularly an institutional (universal, comprehensive) rather than a residual (minimalist, safety net) system. They argue that the concept (a) contradicts the idea of comprehensiveness; (b) leads to unsustainable expenditures; (c) is too indeterminate for policy; and (d) supports only a prioritarian distribution (and therefore a residual system). I argue (a) that ‘comprehensive’ understood as ‘including the full continuum of care’ and ‘medically necessary’ understood as ‘prioritized by medical criteria’ are not contradictory, and (b) that UHC is a solution to the problem of sustainability, not its cause. Those who criticize ‘medical need’ for indeterminacy (c) are not transparent about the source (ethical, semantic, political, or other) of their commitment to their standards of determinacy: they promote standards that are higher than is necessary for legitimate policy, ignoring opportunity costs. Furthermore, the indeterminacy of concepts affects all risk-sharing systems and all systems that rely on medical standard of care. I then argue that (d) the concept of need in itself does not imply a minimal sufficientist standard or a prioritarian distribution; neither does the idea of legitimate public policy dictate that public services be minimalist. The policy choice for a system of health care that is comprehensive and offers as good care as can be achieved when delivered on equal terms and conditions for all is a coherent option.
Footnotes
1
Throughout I refer to Canadian medicare in lower case, to indicate that, unlike US Medicare or the NHS in the UK, it is not a centrally-organized system either of payment or of delivery. Federal standards for the provincial health insurance programs are set by the Canada Health Act [4] and delivery is by diverse public, not-for-profit, and private service providers. The decentralized systems informed by the principles of the CHA but also by various provincial laws and regulations are typically referred to in policy and politics as though they constituted a single system called ‘medicare’.
 
2
I discuss limitations to and qualifications of this claim below.
 
3
E.g. the Health Canada website on Canada’s health care system refers to “the underlying Canadian values of equity and solidarity.” http://​www.​hc-sc.​gc.​ca/​hcs-sss/​medi-assur/​index-eng.​php (visited June 1, 2016; last modified 2010-12-09).
 
4
There are nuances and limitations to this idea of “all Canadians” sharing the same coverage. Coverage is primarily dependent on provincial residency (not just federal citizenship) with a waiting period to establish residency; having coverage is defined as being an “insured person.” Other government-funded programs alongside medicare, or that existed before medicare, include the Interim Federal Health Program for refugees, workers’ compensation schemes, coverage for the armed forces, and the Non-Insured Health Benefits Program for Inuit and First Nations: these provide funding that may replace medicare for certain incidents for otherwise insured persons (workers compensation), or be equivalent to medicare for certain persons insured or non-insured (IFHP, armed forces), or provided services in addition to medicare for certain persons insured or non-insured (IFHP, armed forces, NIHB, workers compensation).
 
5
Substantial empirical concerns can, of course, be raised about whether Canada actually achieves this ideal.
 
6
Flood suggests that keeping management costs low has deprived Canada of the benefits of active management [11, p. 20].
 
7
This view persists in the Vertes report on preferential access in the Alberta health care system [40], which accepts the idea that the clinical judgment of physicians is the appropriate gate-keeping mechanism.
 
8
See Lahey in this volume for a discussion of the ‘locus’ of medicare in Canada.
 
9
A desire to have a need met or an interest in having a need met is a desire or an interest because the need is a need, rather than a needs being a subset of particularly strong desires or interests.
 
10
These dimensions encompass epistemic considerations (our current state of knowledge), technological considerations (what interventions are possible), and social considerations (social agreements and disagreements relating to valued human functionings). These three considerations, while being particularly prominent in each of the respective domains, may also pertain to any of the others.
 
11
Hasman, Hope and Østerdal argue that need in health care should be interpreted in relation to a health state-intervention pairing. Wiggins also claims there can be no need for an intervention that does not exist, and that the need for an intervention is subject to its feasibility in a context. This is a modification of the ordinary concept of need: we would normally say that that persons with ALS need a cure, although health care does not have one to offer. It may be felt that within the scope of the health care system, this is an acceptable and practical limitation. However, women and children in Africa needed prevention of mother-to-child-transmission of HIV/AIDS before it was feasible in that context. The moral imperative in this case changed the standards for feasibility, so that things became feasible.
 
12
The fact that what the market offers one can be constrained indirectly by what one’s fellow market participants choose may be implicitly accepted by Meadowcroft. As noted above, it seems that his arguments should be addressed against a single-tier system that compels (or comes close to compelling) universal participation (pp. 5–6); he argues instead that all systems of UHC impinge on freedom, not limiting this claim to single-tier systems. But non-compulsory systems constrain the choices of those who opt out only insofar as enough market participants are happy with the non-compulsory UHC, take it up, and so exit the private market—and then the private markets have less to offer, limiting the choices of those who have opted out. Absent such a dynamic, the mere existence of a UHC option does not impinge on freedom.
 
13
The former criticism has be advanced forcefully by Harris [17] and shown in the research of Nord et al. [28] to be a perspective often held by non-philosophers.
 
14
Hasman, Hope and Østerdal have taken this approach [18], in contrast to Culyer and Wagstaff [8], who treat acuity of need not as an input to resource allocation but as a determination reached through an allocation process. For deep reasons, the question of severity of need is not always distinguished from the question of equality in treatment—the prioritarian concern can be expressed as one for equal treatment for equally severe needs, whatever the cost of the treatment [41].
 
Literature
1.
go back to reference Broome, J. (1984). Uncertainty and fairness. The Economic Journal, 94, 624–632.CrossRef Broome, J. (1984). Uncertainty and fairness. The Economic Journal, 94, 624–632.CrossRef
2.
go back to reference Broome, J. (1990). Fairness. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 91, 87–101.CrossRef Broome, J. (1990). Fairness. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 91, 87–101.CrossRef
3.
5.
go back to reference Crisp, R. (2002). Treatment according to need: Justice and the British National Health Service. In R. Rhodes, M. P. Battin, & A. Silvers (Eds.), Medicine and social justice: Essays on the distribution of health care (pp. 134–143). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Crisp, R. (2002). Treatment according to need: Justice and the British National Health Service. In R. Rhodes, M. P. Battin, & A. Silvers (Eds.), Medicine and social justice: Essays on the distribution of health care (pp. 134–143). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
6.
go back to reference Crisp, R. (2003). Equality, priority, and compassion. Ethics, 113, 745–763.CrossRef Crisp, R. (2003). Equality, priority, and compassion. Ethics, 113, 745–763.CrossRef
8.
go back to reference Culyer, A. J., & Wagstaff, A. (1993). Equity and equality in health and health care. Journal of Health Economics, 12, 431–457.CrossRefPubMed Culyer, A. J., & Wagstaff, A. (1993). Equity and equality in health and health care. Journal of Health Economics, 12, 431–457.CrossRefPubMed
9.
go back to reference Dawson, A., & Verweij, M. (2012). Solidarity: A moral concept in need of clarification. Public Health Ethics, 5, 1–5.CrossRef Dawson, A., & Verweij, M. (2012). Solidarity: A moral concept in need of clarification. Public Health Ethics, 5, 1–5.CrossRef
10.
go back to reference Dworkin, R. (1993). Justice in the distribution of health care. McGill Law Journal, 38, 883–898.PubMed Dworkin, R. (1993). Justice in the distribution of health care. McGill Law Journal, 38, 883–898.PubMed
11.
go back to reference Flood, C. M. (2000). Arguments in economics and justice for government intervention in health insurance and health services markets. In International health care reform: A legal, economic, and political analysis (pp. 15–40). London: Routledge. Flood, C. M. (2000). Arguments in economics and justice for government intervention in health insurance and health services markets. In International health care reform: A legal, economic, and political analysis (pp. 15–40). London: Routledge.
12.
13.
go back to reference Flood, C. M., & Haugan, A. (2010). Is Canada odd? A comparison of European and Canadian approaches to choice and regulation of the public/private divide in health care. Health Economics, Policy and Law, 5, 319–341.CrossRef Flood, C. M., & Haugan, A. (2010). Is Canada odd? A comparison of European and Canadian approaches to choice and regulation of the public/private divide in health care. Health Economics, Policy and Law, 5, 319–341.CrossRef
14.
go back to reference Gunson, D. (2009). Solidarity and the universal declaration on bioethics and human rights. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 34, 241–260.CrossRefPubMed Gunson, D. (2009). Solidarity and the universal declaration on bioethics and human rights. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 34, 241–260.CrossRefPubMed
15.
go back to reference Hall, E. (1964). Royal commission on health services: Volume 1. Ottawa: Queen’s Printer. Hall, E. (1964). Royal commission on health services: Volume 1. Ottawa: Queen’s Printer.
16.
go back to reference Hall, E. (1965). Royal commission on health services: Volume 2. Ottawa: Queen’s Printer. Hall, E. (1965). Royal commission on health services: Volume 2. Ottawa: Queen’s Printer.
17.
go back to reference Harris, J. (1988). More and better justice. Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series, 23, 75–96.CrossRef Harris, J. (1988). More and better justice. Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series, 23, 75–96.CrossRef
18.
go back to reference Hasman, A., Hope, T., & Østerdal, L. P. (2006). Health care need: Three interpretations. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 23, 145–156.CrossRefPubMed Hasman, A., Hope, T., & Østerdal, L. P. (2006). Health care need: Three interpretations. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 23, 145–156.CrossRefPubMed
19.
go back to reference Heath, J. (2011). Three normative models of the welfare state. Public Reason, 3, 13–43. Heath, J. (2011). Three normative models of the welfare state. Public Reason, 3, 13–43.
20.
go back to reference Houtepen, R., & ter Meulen, R. (2000). New types of solidarity in the European welfare state. Health Care Analysis, 8, 329–340.CrossRefPubMed Houtepen, R., & ter Meulen, R. (2000). New types of solidarity in the European welfare state. Health Care Analysis, 8, 329–340.CrossRefPubMed
21.
go back to reference Juth, N. (2015). Challenges for principles of need in health care. Health Care Analysis, 23, 73–87.CrossRefPubMed Juth, N. (2015). Challenges for principles of need in health care. Health Care Analysis, 23, 73–87.CrossRefPubMed
22.
go back to reference Kolers, A. (2012). Dynamics of solidarity. Journal of Political Philosophy, 20, 365–383.CrossRef Kolers, A. (2012). Dynamics of solidarity. Journal of Political Philosophy, 20, 365–383.CrossRef
23.
go back to reference Kolers, A. (2014). The priority of solidarity to justice. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 31, 420–433.CrossRef Kolers, A. (2014). The priority of solidarity to justice. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 31, 420–433.CrossRef
24.
go back to reference Krishnamurthy, M. (2013). Political solidarity, justice and public health. Public Health Ethics, 6, 129–141.CrossRef Krishnamurthy, M. (2013). Political solidarity, justice and public health. Public Health Ethics, 6, 129–141.CrossRef
25.
go back to reference Krogsbøll, L. T., Jørgensen, K. J., & Gøtzsche, P. C. (2013). General health checks in adults for reducing morbidity and mortality from disease. JAMA, 309(23), 2489–2490.CrossRefPubMed Krogsbøll, L. T., Jørgensen, K. J., & Gøtzsche, P. C. (2013). General health checks in adults for reducing morbidity and mortality from disease. JAMA, 309(23), 2489–2490.CrossRefPubMed
26.
go back to reference Lehtonen, T., & Liukko, J. (2015). Producing solidarity, inequality and exclusion through insurance. Res Publica, 21, 155–169.CrossRef Lehtonen, T., & Liukko, J. (2015). Producing solidarity, inequality and exclusion through insurance. Res Publica, 21, 155–169.CrossRef
27.
go back to reference Meadowcroft, J. (2015). Just healthcare? The moral failure of single-tier basic healthcare. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 40, 152–168.CrossRefPubMed Meadowcroft, J. (2015). Just healthcare? The moral failure of single-tier basic healthcare. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 40, 152–168.CrossRefPubMed
28.
go back to reference Nord, E., Richardson, J., Street, A., Kuhse, H., & Singer, P. (1995). Who cares about cost? Does economic analysis impose or reflect social values? Health Policy, 34, 79–94.CrossRefPubMed Nord, E., Richardson, J., Street, A., Kuhse, H., & Singer, P. (1995). Who cares about cost? Does economic analysis impose or reflect social values? Health Policy, 34, 79–94.CrossRefPubMed
29.
go back to reference Persad, G., Wertheimer, A., & Emanuel, E. J. (2009). Principles for allocation of scarce medical interventions. Lancet, 373, 423–431.CrossRefPubMed Persad, G., Wertheimer, A., & Emanuel, E. J. (2009). Principles for allocation of scarce medical interventions. Lancet, 373, 423–431.CrossRefPubMed
32.
go back to reference Reid, L. (2016). Answering the empirical challenge to arguments for universal health coverage based in health equity. Public Health Ethics (advance access). Reid, L. (2016). Answering the empirical challenge to arguments for universal health coverage based in health equity. Public Health Ethics (advance access).
33.
go back to reference Reid, L. (2016). Concierge, wellness, and block fee models in primary care: Ethical and regulatory concerns. Health Care Analysis (this issue). Reid, L. (2016). Concierge, wellness, and block fee models in primary care: Ethical and regulatory concerns. Health Care Analysis (this issue).
34.
go back to reference Reid, L. (2016). Introduction to the special issue: Precarious solidarity: Preferential access in Canadian health care. Health Care Analysis (this issue). Reid, L. (2016). Introduction to the special issue: Precarious solidarity: Preferential access in Canadian health care. Health Care Analysis (this issue).
35.
go back to reference Schut, F. T., & van de Ven, W. P. (2011). Effects of purchaser competition in the Dutch health system: Is the glass half full or half empty? Health Economics, Policy and Law, 6, 109–123.CrossRef Schut, F. T., & van de Ven, W. P. (2011). Effects of purchaser competition in the Dutch health system: Is the glass half full or half empty? Health Economics, Policy and Law, 6, 109–123.CrossRef
37.
go back to reference Sen, A. (2009). Capitalism beyond the crisis. The New York Review of Books, 56(5), 27–30. Sen, A. (2009). Capitalism beyond the crisis. The New York Review of Books, 56(5), 27–30.
38.
go back to reference Snyder, J., Johnston, R., Crooks, V., Morgan, J., & Adams, K. (2016). How medical tourism enables preferential access to care: Four patterns from the Canadian context. Health Care Analysis (this issue). Snyder, J., Johnston, R., Crooks, V., Morgan, J., & Adams, K. (2016). How medical tourism enables preferential access to care: Four patterns from the Canadian context. Health Care Analysis (this issue).
39.
go back to reference Tobin, J. (1970). On limiting the domain of inequality. Journal of Law and Economics, 13, 263–277.CrossRef Tobin, J. (1970). On limiting the domain of inequality. Journal of Law and Economics, 13, 263–277.CrossRef
41.
go back to reference Wagstaff, A. (1991). QALYs and the equity-efficiency trade-off. Journal of Health Economics, 10, 21–41.CrossRefPubMed Wagstaff, A. (1991). QALYs and the equity-efficiency trade-off. Journal of Health Economics, 10, 21–41.CrossRefPubMed
42.
go back to reference Weale, A. (1990). Equality, social solidarity, and the welfare state. Ethics, 100, 473–488.CrossRef Weale, A. (1990). Equality, social solidarity, and the welfare state. Ethics, 100, 473–488.CrossRef
43.
go back to reference Wiggins, D. (1998). Needs, values, truth: Essays in the philosophy of value. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1987). Wiggins, D. (1998). Needs, values, truth: Essays in the philosophy of value. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1987).
44.
go back to reference Williams, A. (1995). Economics, QALYs and medical ethics: A health economist’s perspective. Health Care Analysis, 3, 221–226.CrossRefPubMed Williams, A. (1995). Economics, QALYs and medical ethics: A health economist’s perspective. Health Care Analysis, 3, 221–226.CrossRefPubMed
Metadata
Title
Medical Need: Evaluating a Conceptual Critique of Universal Health Coverage
Author
Lynette Reid
Publication date
01-06-2017
Publisher
Springer US
Published in
Health Care Analysis / Issue 2/2017
Print ISSN: 1065-3058
Electronic ISSN: 1573-3394
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-016-0325-3

Other articles of this Issue 2/2017

Health Care Analysis 2/2017 Go to the issue