Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Health Care Analysis 3/2007

01-09-2007 | Original Article

Varied and Principled Understandings of Autonomy in English Law: Justifiable Inconsistency or Blinkered Moralism?

Author: John Coggon

Published in: Health Care Analysis | Issue 3/2007

Login to get access

Abstract

Autonomy is a concept that holds much appeal to social and legal philosophers. Within a medical context, it is often argued that it should be afforded supremacy over other concepts and interests. When respect for autonomy merely requires non-intervention, an adult’s right to refuse treatment is held at law to be absolute. This apparently simple statement of principle does not hold true in practice. This is in part because an individual must be found to be competent to make a valid refusal of consent to medical treatment, and capacity to decide is not an absolute concept. But further to this, I argue that there are three relevant understandings of autonomy within our society, and each can demand in differing cases that different courses of action be followed. Judges, perhaps inadvertently, have been able to take advantage of the equivocal nature of the concept to come tacitly to decisions that reflect their own moral judgments of patients or decisions made in particular cases. The result is the inconsistent application of principle. I ask whether this is an unforeseen outcome or if it reflects a wilful disregard for equal treatment in favour of silent moral judgments in legal cases. Whatever the cause, I suggest that once this practice is seen to occur, acceptable justification of it in some cases is difficult to find.
Footnotes
1
Respect for autonomy is one of the “four principles”: see [6]. On the applicability and utility of the “four principles” in UK medical practice, see [20, 21]. On the history of autonomy, see [56].
 
2
Consider, for example, the statement of Ward LJ in [48, p. 726]: “This court is a court of law, not of morals, and our task has been to find, and our duty is then to apply the relevant principles of law.” This statement may be met with some due cynicism. Preferable is the statement of Browne-Wilkinson L in [2, pp. 879–880]: “[I]f the judges seek to develop new law to regulate the new circumstances, the law so laid down will of necessity reflect judges’ views on the underlying ethical questions, questions on which there is a legitimate division of opinion.”
 
3
See paragraphs 81–83, 94. The paper referred to is Kim Atkins [4].
 
4
A right under Article 8 of the European Convention on Human Rights, for example, is not absolute. Derogation is made possible by Article 8(2). The common law right to exercise autonomy through a competent refusal of treatment, however, is absolute.
 
5
Consider, e.g., Hoffmann LJ in [2, p. 826]; Lord Phillips MR in [43] at paragraph 30. Although contrast the approach of Dame Elizabeth Butler-Sloss: in [39, p. 361] she states “[A]rticle 8 protects the right to personal autonomy, otherwise described as the right to bodily integrity”, thus holding that a permanently unconscious patient is still autonomous. In some cases, there is no reference to ‘autonomy’ at all, and instead matters relating to ‘self-determination’ are considered; for example, [58]; in other cases autonomy is not described or explained, but is merely asserted; for example, [49].
 
6
This raises some interesting questions: What damages would be appropriate for a breach of autonomy? Is a breach of autonomy all-or-nothing, or is it relative? Does the potential physical effect of a breach of autonomy affect the severity of the breach of autonomy?
 
7
In the case of In Re MB [30], Butler-Sloss LJ endorsed Thorpe J’s approach. She at one point approves just the first and third stages, but elsewhere in the judgment all three aspects of Thorpe J’s test are endorsed.
 
8
The exception to this rule is found in section 63 of the Mental Health Act 1983, which denies patients the right to refuse consent to medical treatment given for the mental disorder from which they are suffering, unless it is treatment falling within section 57 or 58.
 
9
Against the odds, in Re C, the patient did not actually die as a result of his refusal.
 
10
The decision in this case was overruled, but much of the law stated in the lengthy judgment is good. The statement in the paragraph cited here may safely be taken to reflect the law’s attitude.
 
11
Mental Capacity Act 2005, sections 24–26.
 
12
Although he does not use the terms that I do to describe the conceptions of autonomy, many of the ideas here can be found in Richard Lindley Autonomy [34].
 
13
My thanks to Professor Søren Holm for pointing out this distinction to me.
 
14
It might be argued that acting in accordance with best desire autonomy is better described as acting with ‘soft paternalism’—i.e., self-inflicted paternalism—rather than autonomy: [3].
 
15
See also [34, chapter 5].
 
16
Contrast Joseph Raz’s account [47, pp. 412–413]. According to this, the harm principle includes protecting a person from harming himself as well as others.
 
17
For which, see [61, chapters 6 and 19; 22, chapters 13 and 16].
 
19
Arguably it is not: if I want to kill someone but I want not to go to jail more, then my current desire autonomy might not be thwarted; I may just be upset by the necessity I perceive in my choice.
 
20
See, for example, [4, 7, 12, 14, 27, 35, 40, 62pp. 51–67].
 
21
These examples are taken from [3].
 
22
It is important not to misunderstand ‘irrationality’. The refusal, for example, of a Jehovah’s Witness to receive a blood transfusion is not irrational given the perceived alternative. Of course, it is arguable that the belief itself is irrational.
 
23
This may apply even to liberal theorists. Consider, for example, Ronald Dworkin’s discussion on ‘critical interests’: [13, pp. 192–193].
 
24
Butler-Sloss LJ: “A mentally competent patient has an absolute right to refuse to consent to medical treatment for any reason, rational or irrational, or for no reason at all, even where that decision may lead to his or her own death” [30, p. 432].
 
25
See supra, n. 8.
 
26
This was confirmed in St George’s Healthcare NHS Trust v S [63]: a pregnant woman may refuse her consent for any or no reason. Of course, capacity may well be questioned, and a lack of capacity may still result in a caesarean section being allowed: In Bolton Hospitals NHS Trust v O [8], it was found that the irrationality of the patient’s actions marked a lack of competence.
 
27
The risk that judicial care (or other motives) might lead to unacceptable breaches of autonomy is well demonstrated by the ‘caesarean cases’. For consideration of the issues in this area, see [57].
 
28
The decision was actually based on the Mental Health Act 1983, section 63, but the judge went on to consider the applicability of the law were the force-feeding not to be considered as treatment. Unlike B v. Croydon HA [5] the judge also found a lack of capacity in Brady’s case. See supra, n. 8.
 
29
Dame Elizabeth Butler-Sloss rejected the conspiracy theory claims without much explicit consideration. This was possibly in part to avoid being bound by the point in Re C that a refusal based on reasoning linked to the patient’s disorder would have meant that capacity would have been diminished. See supra, n. 8.
 
30
Linked both to conceptions of justice and the protection of prisoners’ physical health.
 
31
As was noted in a commentary on the case, “It must have been difficult for Maurice Kay J to put from his mind the fact that Brady is a perverted and sadistic child torturer and killer, and one of the most hated men in Britain.” [15, p. 255].
 
32
For judicial expression of this right, see note 24.
 
33
In Re C and Robb it seems more appropriate to consider the attitude towards the patients as being one of indifference rather than one seeking punishment.
 
Literature
1.
go back to reference Adshead, G. (2003). Commentary on Szasz. Journal of Medical Ethics, 29, 230–232.CrossRef Adshead, G. (2003). Commentary on Szasz. Journal of Medical Ethics, 29, 230–232.CrossRef
2.
go back to reference Airedale NHS Trust v. Bland. (1993) AC 789. Airedale NHS Trust v. Bland. (1993) AC 789.
3.
go back to reference Anonymous. (2006). The state is looking after you. The Economist (06/04/2006), 13. Anonymous. (2006). The state is looking after you. The Economist (06/04/2006), 13.
4.
go back to reference Atkins, K. (2000). Autonomy and the subjective character of experience. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 17(1), 71–79.PubMedCrossRef Atkins, K. (2000). Autonomy and the subjective character of experience. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 17(1), 71–79.PubMedCrossRef
5.
6.
go back to reference Beauchamp, T. L., & Childress J. F. (2001). Principles of Biomedical Ethics (5th ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. Beauchamp, T. L., & Childress J. F. (2001). Principles of Biomedical Ethics (5th ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.
7.
go back to reference Biggs, H. (2003). A pretty fine line: Life, death, autonomy and letting it B. Feminist Legal Studies, 11, 291–301.CrossRef Biggs, H. (2003). A pretty fine line: Life, death, autonomy and letting it B. Feminist Legal Studies, 11, 291–301.CrossRef
8.
go back to reference Bolton Hospitals NHS Trust v. O. (2003). 1 FLR 824. Bolton Hospitals NHS Trust v. O. (2003). 1 FLR 824.
9.
go back to reference Brazier, M. (2005). Where the law and ethics conflict? Research Ethics Review, 1, 3, 97–100. Brazier, M. (2005). Where the law and ethics conflict? Research Ethics Review, 1, 3, 97–100.
10.
11.
12.
go back to reference Dworkin, G. (1988). The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Dworkin, G. (1988). The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
13.
go back to reference Dworkin, R. (1993). Life’s dominion. Harper Collins. Dworkin, R. (1993). Life’s dominion. Harper Collins.
14.
go back to reference Fagan, A. (2004). Challenging the bioethical application of the autonomy principle with multicultural societies. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 21(1), 15–31.PubMedCrossRef Fagan, A. (2004). Challenging the bioethical application of the autonomy principle with multicultural societies. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 21(1), 15–31.PubMedCrossRef
15.
go back to reference Fennell, P. (2000). Detained psychiatric patient: Forcible feeding and the right to die. Medical Law Review, 8, 251–256.CrossRef Fennell, P. (2000). Detained psychiatric patient: Forcible feeding and the right to die. Medical Law Review, 8, 251–256.CrossRef
16.
go back to reference Finnis, J. (1997). A philosophical case against euthanasia. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical, and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Finnis, J. (1997). A philosophical case against euthanasia. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical, and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
17.
go back to reference Finnis, J. (1997). The fragile case for euthanasia: a reply to John Harris. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical, and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Finnis, J. (1997). The fragile case for euthanasia: a reply to John Harris. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical, and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
18.
go back to reference Finnis, J. (1997). Misunderstanding the case against euthanasia: Response to Harris’s first reply. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical, and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Finnis, J. (1997). Misunderstanding the case against euthanasia: Response to Harris’s first reply. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical, and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
19.
go back to reference Frankfurt, H. G. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, 68(1), 5–20.CrossRef Frankfurt, H. G. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, 68(1), 5–20.CrossRef
20.
go back to reference Gillon, R. (1986). Philosophical medical ethics. Chichester: Wiley. Gillon, R. (1986). Philosophical medical ethics. Chichester: Wiley.
21.
go back to reference Gillon, R. (1994). Medical ethics: Four principles plus attention to scope. British Medical Journal, 309, 184.PubMed Gillon, R. (1994). Medical ethics: Four principles plus attention to scope. British Medical Journal, 309, 184.PubMed
22.
go back to reference Glover, J. (1977). Causing death and saving lives. Penguin. Glover, J. (1977). Causing death and saving lives. Penguin.
23.
go back to reference Gylling, H. A. (2004). Autonomy revisited. Cambridge Quaterly of Healthcare Ethics, 13, 41–46. Gylling, H. A. (2004). Autonomy revisited. Cambridge Quaterly of Healthcare Ethics, 13, 41–46.
24.
go back to reference Harris, J. (1997). Euthanasia and the value of life. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical, and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Harris, J. (1997). Euthanasia and the value of life. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical, and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
25.
go back to reference Harris, J. (1997). The philosophical case against the philosophical case against euthanasia. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical, and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Harris, J. (1997). The philosophical case against the philosophical case against euthanasia. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical, and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
26.
go back to reference Harris, J. (1997). Final thoughts on final acts. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical, and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Harris, J. (1997). Final thoughts on final acts. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical, and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
27.
28.
go back to reference HE v. A Hospital NHS Trust. (2003). EWHC 1017. HE v. A Hospital NHS Trust. (2003). EWHC 1017.
29.
go back to reference Hornett, S. (1997). Advance directives: A legal and ethical analysis. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hornett, S. (1997). Advance directives: A legal and ethical analysis. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical and legal perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
30.
go back to reference In Re MB (Medical treatment). (1997). 2 FLR 426. In Re MB (Medical treatment). (1997). 2 FLR 426.
31.
go back to reference In Re T (Adult: Refusal of treatment). (1993). Fam 95. In Re T (Adult: Refusal of treatment). (1993). Fam 95.
33.
go back to reference Kant, I. (1998). In M. Gregor (Ed.), Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kant, I. (1998). In M. Gregor (Ed.), Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
34.
go back to reference Lindley, R. (1986). Autonomy. Basingstoke: MacMillan. Lindley, R. (1986). Autonomy. Basingstoke: MacMillan.
35.
go back to reference Matthews, E. (2000). Autonomy and the psychiatric patient. Journal Applied Philosophy, 17(1), 59–70.CrossRef Matthews, E. (2000). Autonomy and the psychiatric patient. Journal Applied Philosophy, 17(1), 59–70.CrossRef
36.
go back to reference McMillan, J. R. (2003). Dangerousness, mental disorder, and responsibility. Journal of Medical Ethics, 29, 232–235.PubMedCrossRef McMillan, J. R. (2003). Dangerousness, mental disorder, and responsibility. Journal of Medical Ethics, 29, 232–235.PubMedCrossRef
37.
go back to reference Mill, J. S. (1999). In E. Alexander (Ed.), On Liberty. Broadview. Mill, J. S. (1999). In E. Alexander (Ed.), On Liberty. Broadview.
38.
go back to reference Ms B v. An NHS Hospital Trust. (2002). 2 All ER 449. Ms B v. An NHS Hospital Trust. (2002). 2 All ER 449.
39.
go back to reference NHS Trust A v. M and NHS Trust B v H. (2001). Fam 348. NHS Trust A v. M and NHS Trust B v H. (2001). Fam 348.
40.
go back to reference O’Neill, O. (2002). Autonomy and trust in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. O’Neill, O. (2002). Autonomy and trust in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
41.
go back to reference Pretty v. United Kingdom. (2002). 35 EHRR 1. Pretty v. United Kingdom. (2002). 35 EHRR 1.
42.
go back to reference R (On the Application of Oliver Leslie Burke) v. The General Medical Council, The Disability Rights Commission, The Official Solicitor to the Supreme Court. (2004). WL 1640202. R (On the Application of Oliver Leslie Burke) v. The General Medical Council, The Disability Rights Commission, The Official Solicitor to the Supreme Court. (2004). WL 1640202.
43.
go back to reference R (On the Application of Oliver Leslie Burke) v. The General Medical Council. (2005). EWCA Civ 1003. R (On the Application of Oliver Leslie Burke) v. The General Medical Council. (2005). EWCA Civ 1003.
44.
go back to reference R v. Collins and another, ex parte Brady. (2000). 58 BMLR 173. R v. Collins and another, ex parte Brady. (2000). 58 BMLR 173.
46.
go back to reference R v. North West Lancashire health authority, ex parte A, D and G. (1999). Lloyd’s Report on Medicine, 399. R v. North West Lancashire health authority, ex parte A, D and G. (1999). Lloyd’s Report on Medicine, 399.
47.
go back to reference Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
48.
go back to reference Re A (Children) (Conjoined Twins: Medical Treatment) No. 1. (2000). HRLR 721. Re A (Children) (Conjoined Twins: Medical Treatment) No. 1. (2000). HRLR 721.
49.
go back to reference Re C (Adult: Refusal of Medical Treatment). (1994). 2 FCR 151. Re C (Adult: Refusal of Medical Treatment). (1994). 2 FCR 151.
54.
go back to reference Savulescu, J. (2006). Conscientious objection in medicine. British Medical Journal, 332, 294–297.PubMedCrossRef Savulescu, J. (2006). Conscientious objection in medicine. British Medical Journal, 332, 294–297.PubMedCrossRef
55.
go back to reference Sayers, G. M. (2003). Psychiatry and the control of dangerousness: A comment. Journal of Medical Ethics, 29, 235–236.PubMedCrossRef Sayers, G. M. (2003). Psychiatry and the control of dangerousness: A comment. Journal of Medical Ethics, 29, 235–236.PubMedCrossRef
56.
go back to reference Schneewind, J. B. (1997). The invention of autonomy: A history of modern moral philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Schneewind, J. B. (1997). The invention of autonomy: A history of modern moral philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
57.
go back to reference Scott, R. (2000). The pregnant woman and the good Samaritan—can a woman have a duty to undergo a caesarean section? Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 20(3), 407–436.PubMedCrossRef Scott, R. (2000). The pregnant woman and the good Samaritan—can a woman have a duty to undergo a caesarean section? Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 20(3), 407–436.PubMedCrossRef
58.
go back to reference Secretary of State for the Home Department v. Robb. (1995). Fam 127. Secretary of State for the Home Department v. Robb. (1995). Fam 127.
59.
go back to reference Sidaway v. Board of Governors of the Bethlem Royal Hospital. (1985). AC 871. Sidaway v. Board of Governors of the Bethlem Royal Hospital. (1985). AC 871.
60.
go back to reference Skrabanek, P. (1994). The death of humane medicine and the rise of coercive healthism. Bury St Edmunds: St Edmundsbury Press. Skrabanek, P. (1994). The death of humane medicine and the rise of coercive healthism. Bury St Edmunds: St Edmundsbury Press.
61.
go back to reference Somerville, M. (2001). Death talk—the case against euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press. Somerville, M. (2001). Death talk—the case against euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.
62.
go back to reference Spiers, J. (1997). Who owns our bodies? Making moral choices in health care. Radcliffe: Medical Press. Spiers, J. (1997). Who owns our bodies? Making moral choices in health care. Radcliffe: Medical Press.
63.
go back to reference St George’s Healthcare NHS Trust v. S. (1998). 3 WLR 936. St George’s Healthcare NHS Trust v. S. (1998). 3 WLR 936.
64.
go back to reference Szasz, T. (2003). Psychiatry and the control of dangerousness: on the apotropaic function of the term “mental illness”. Journal of Medicine Ethics, 29, 227–230.CrossRef Szasz, T. (2003). Psychiatry and the control of dangerousness: on the apotropaic function of the term “mental illness”. Journal of Medicine Ethics, 29, 227–230.CrossRef
65.
Metadata
Title
Varied and Principled Understandings of Autonomy in English Law: Justifiable Inconsistency or Blinkered Moralism?
Author
John Coggon
Publication date
01-09-2007
Publisher
Springer US
Published in
Health Care Analysis / Issue 3/2007
Print ISSN: 1065-3058
Electronic ISSN: 1573-3394
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-007-0062-8

Other articles of this Issue 3/2007

Health Care Analysis 3/2007 Go to the issue

Original Article

L.I.F.E. and D.E.A.T.H