Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2/2011

01-05-2011 | Scientific Contribution

DSM diagnosis and beyond: on the need for a hermeneutically-informed biopsychosocial framework

Author: Paul Healy

Published in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy | Issue 2/2011

Login to get access

Abstract

While often dubbed “the bible of contemporary psychiatry” and widely hailed as providing “a benchmark” for the profession, on closer inspection the DSM is seen to be shot through with philosophical assumptions that restrict its theoretical cogency and limit it clinical efficacy. Hence, in the interests of enhanced patient-care it is important to think critically about the DSM, with a view to maximising its diagnostic strengths while minimising its weaknesses. The critical analysis undertaken in the present paper underscores the importance of not construing the DSM as a self-contained diagnostic tool but of viewing it, rather, as an indispensable component in a more comprehensive, multidimensional diagnostic process. More specifically, the contention is that the DSM’s diagnostic limitations evoke a biopsychosocial framework of application as their necessary corrective, notwithstanding the entrenched tendency to construe these approaches as oppositional. Further, it is contended that a hermeneutically informed biopsychosocial template has particular advantages as an integrating framework.
Footnotes
1
The fourth edition of the DSM was published in 1994 (and revised in 2000). However, since the core philosophical presuppositions discussed in this paper were introduced with the publication of DSM-III and to date continue to be its predominant philosophical influences, this diagnostic manual will be referred to here simply as “DSM”, without differentiation between DSM-III and DSM-IV unless the context necessitates a more specific reference.
 
2
These criteria are often referred to as “Feighner criteria” after the Washington University psychiatrist who initially formulated them. As delineated by Moller (2008, p. 55), the general formulation is that: “in order to make diagnosis D, the patient must present with Symptom A together with one of the symptoms from the series B, C and E, but symptoms P. and O may not be present”.
 
3
Preparations for DSM-V are currently advanced, and publication is anticipated around May 2013.
 
4
To set these presuppositions in context and to clarify both how they are interrelated and how they pervade this diagnostic model, it is important at this juncture to register their Kraepelinian origins (i.e. deriving from the groundbreaking conceptual innovations introduced by Emil Kraepelin in the late nineteenth century). Referencing the 6th (1899) edition of Kraepelin’s Psychiatrie, Mundt and Backerstrass succinctly epitomise the nature, direction, and extent of Kraepelin’s continued influence on the conceptualisation of the core DSM model as follows (2005, p. 220):
Emil Kraepelin emphasised the medical model for psychiatric diagnosis, and made this model most pervasive in the history of psychiatry. According to his concept, diagnostic classification was based on the convergence of psychopathological symptoms, aetiology, course, outcome, brain morphology, and pathophysiology. Those patients who show the same characteristics in most of these domains can be considered as belonging to one nosological category which Kraepelin considered a “natural entity”. In his view, the research process follows a continued approximation to perfect accuracy by grouping patients ever tighter according to [these] criteria.
But notwithstanding his extensive tutelary influence, Kraepelin’s doctrines were not taken over unadulterated, but rather via a nine-point neo-Kraepelinian “credo” (as Harvard psychologist Gerald Klerman termed it) informing the conceptualisation of the DSM model (Decker 2007, p. 248). Of particular relevance for what follows are the emphatic neo-Kraepelinian contentions that: “Psychiatry is a branch of medicine”; “There are discrete mental illnesses”; “The focus of psychiatric physicians should be particularly on the biological aspects of mental illness”; “There should be explicit and intentional concern with diagnosis and classification” (indeed, the neo-Kraepelinians tended toward the view that “classification is diagnosis”); and that “Diagnostic criteria should be [explicitly] codified”.
For detailed technical analyses of the extent of Kraepelin’s ongoing pervasive influence on the DSM model notwithstanding refinements instantiated in DSM-IV and for textured commentary on possible future directions, the interested reader should consult the recent special issue of the European Archives of Psychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience (Vol. 258, Supp. 2, June 2008) devoted to this topic. The succinct Editors’ Introduction (pp. 1–2) and the contribution by Hans–Jurgen Moller (pp. 48–73) are of particular interest from the perspective of present concerns.
 
5
Strong DSM advocates may contend that clinicians could not fail to attend to the experiential, or “phenomenological”, dimension of the patient’s experience. While this may be so in an informal everyday sense, the point at issue here is that given its biomedical proclivities, its categorical focus and positivistic biases, this crucial dimension is not formally part of the DSM model. On the contrary, as already noted, the DSM continues to be motivated by the neo-Kraepelinian credo that “classification is diagnosis”. Moreover, the DSM’s strong biomedical orientation lends itself to treating the experiential as an epiphenomenon, to be quickly transcended in the interests of getting on with the business of concluding a “truly scientific” diagnosis.
 
6
“Mental pathology, Kraepelin proposed, could be divided into discrete disorders, distinguishable one from the other. Each with its own symptomatology and course; each with its own specific pathophysiology. Nosology [disease classification], according to Kraepelin should be the principal guideline in exploring the biological roots of mental pathology” (van Praag 2008, p. 29).
 
7
The development of a biopsychosocial template in psychiatry is associated with the innovative work of George Engel in particular, and before that of Adolf Meyer (see further Pilgrim 2002; also Borrell-Carrio et al. 2004; Ghaemi 2003, ch. 1).
 
8
Briefly stated, Ghaemi’s thesis is that a biopsychosocial orientation has come to stand for an injunction to include a bit of everything, thereby facilitating the formulation of vague and indiscriminate diagnoses and treatment plans; and hence needs to be replaced by a methodologically-aware “pluralism”, which would avoid the problematic eclectic groundlessness. In effect, however, Ghaemi’s thesis is undermined by his conflation of eclecticism (which he rightly criticises) with biopsychosocial thinking, and his consequent rejection of the latter. Although space limitations preclude its comprehensive defence here, my contention—reflected in the delineation of strengths and possibilities that follows--is that a biopsychosocial orientation is in fact altogether compatible with the “pluralism” that Ghaemi advocates as an antidote to both “dogmatic” (biomedical) monism and eclecticism. Hence, in my view, his arguments in favour of pluralism actually reinforce the position defended here, although this is masked by his trenchant (but unjustified) condemnation of the “biopsychosocial model”. Further, I would contend that the hermeneutic framework delineated hereunder is as much needed to give an integrating focus to Ghaemi’s pluralism as to the biopsychosocial template under elaboration here.
 
9
Accordingly, I typically use the phrase template (or cognates such as framework, approach, orientation) rather than “model” to characterise a biopsychosocial orientation to psychiatric diagnosis and treatment, both to differentiate it from existing biopsychosocial “models” and because the latter term can have (positivistic, biomedical) connotations more commensurate with the aims and aspirations of the DSM approach than with this more expansive diagnostic framework (cf. McLaren 1998).
 
10
Importantly, it should also be borne in mind that, like the DSM itself, the biopsychosocial template needs to be conceptualised as a work in progress in need of continual revision and refinement. Hence, attention needs to be focussed on its strengths and possibilities as a counterbalance to the restrictive DSM model, and not equated with some outdated, or otherwise flawed, historical formulation. Accordingly, the aim here is to highlight some interrelated diagnostic possibilities inherent in this approach as a needed corrective for the DSM’s diagnostic limitations, and to indicate how a hermeneutic underpinning can help give it the requisite theoretical grounding to inure it against charges of groundlessness and eclecticism.
Cognisant that readers may not already be familiar with core tenets of hermeneutic philosophy, deriving from the work of theorists such as Dilthey, Heidegger, and especially Hans-Georg Gadamer, in what follows I have sought to elucidate the core biopsychosocial implications of a hermeneutic orientation in a way that does not presuppose prior acquaintance. But readers who would like to enhance their understanding of the philosophical background may wish to consult, e.g. Alcoff 1996: chs 1 & 2; Grondin 1994: chs VI & VII; Healy 2005: ch. 2.
 
11
In a recent contribution, Tim Thornton has challenged the tenability of the Windelband’s idiographic/nomothetic distinction, and hence the tenability of idiographic understanding as an integral component of comprehensive psychiatric diagnosis (Thornton 2008). While Thornton’s analysis clearly establishes that the idiographic and the nomothetic should not be construed as mutually exclusive and that it is indeed difficult to delimit clearly the boundaries between the two, I would nonetheless contend that, as the World Psychiatric Association enjoins, the distinction can, and should, be used to differentiate in practice between a preoccupation with categorical diagnosis and attention to the particularities of the individual case, and to underscore the point that an adequate diagnosis requires both. Accordingly, it would not do to dispense with this distinction notwithstanding its inevitably fuzzy boundaries.
 
12
See further Phillips (2004) for elaboration and defence of its ongoing, albeit evolving, significance in the diagnostic context.
 
Literature
go back to reference Alcoff, L.M. 1996. Real knowing. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Alcoff, L.M. 1996. Real knowing. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
go back to reference American Psychiatric Association. 1994. DSM-IV: Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association. American Psychiatric Association. 1994. DSM-IV: Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.
go back to reference Andreasen, N.C. 2007. DSM and the death of phenomenology in America: An example of unintended consequences. Schizophrenia Bulletin 33: 108–112.PubMedCrossRef Andreasen, N.C. 2007. DSM and the death of phenomenology in America: An example of unintended consequences. Schizophrenia Bulletin 33: 108–112.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Arnason, V. 2000. Gadamerian dialogue in the patient-professional interaction. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy: A European Journal 3: 17–23.CrossRef Arnason, V. 2000. Gadamerian dialogue in the patient-professional interaction. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy: A European Journal 3: 17–23.CrossRef
go back to reference Bem, S., and H. Looren De Jong. 2006. Theoretical issues in psychology: An introduction. London: Sage. Bem, S., and H. Looren De Jong. 2006. Theoretical issues in psychology: An introduction. London: Sage.
go back to reference Berganza, C.E., J.E. Mezzich, and C. Pouncey. 2005. Concepts of disease: Their relevance for psychiatric diagnosis and classification. Psychopathology 38: 166–170.PubMedCrossRef Berganza, C.E., J.E. Mezzich, and C. Pouncey. 2005. Concepts of disease: Their relevance for psychiatric diagnosis and classification. Psychopathology 38: 166–170.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Borrell-Carrio, F., A.L. Suchman, and R.M. Epstein. 2004. The biopsychosocial model 25 years later: Principles, practice, and scientific inquiry. Annals of Family Medicine 2: 576–582.PubMedCrossRef Borrell-Carrio, F., A.L. Suchman, and R.M. Epstein. 2004. The biopsychosocial model 25 years later: Principles, practice, and scientific inquiry. Annals of Family Medicine 2: 576–582.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Brown, H.I. 1990. Rationality. London: Routledge. Brown, H.I. 1990. Rationality. London: Routledge.
go back to reference Chessick, R.D. 1995. The application of phenomenology to psychiatry and psychotherapy. American Journal of Psychotherapy 49: 159–162.PubMed Chessick, R.D. 1995. The application of phenomenology to psychiatry and psychotherapy. American Journal of Psychotherapy 49: 159–162.PubMed
go back to reference Decker, H.S. 2007. How Kraepelinian was Kraepelin? How Kraepelinian are the neo-Kraepelinians?—From Emil Kraepelin to DSM-III. History of Psychiatry 18: 337–360.PubMedCrossRef Decker, H.S. 2007. How Kraepelinian was Kraepelin? How Kraepelinian are the neo-Kraepelinians?—From Emil Kraepelin to DSM-III. History of Psychiatry 18: 337–360.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Eaton, J. 1998. Gadamer: Psychotherapy as conversation. European Journal of Psychotherapy & Counselling 1: 421–433.CrossRef Eaton, J. 1998. Gadamer: Psychotherapy as conversation. European Journal of Psychotherapy & Counselling 1: 421–433.CrossRef
go back to reference Eriksen, K., and V.E. Kress. 2005. Beyond the DSM story: Ethical quandaries, challenges, and best practices. Thousand Oaks, CA US: Sage. Eriksen, K., and V.E. Kress. 2005. Beyond the DSM story: Ethical quandaries, challenges, and best practices. Thousand Oaks, CA US: Sage.
go back to reference Fulford, K.W.M. 2005. Values in psychiatric diagnosis: Developments in policy, training and research. Psychopathology 38: 171–176.PubMedCrossRef Fulford, K.W.M. 2005. Values in psychiatric diagnosis: Developments in policy, training and research. Psychopathology 38: 171–176.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Gadamer, H.-G. 1989. Truth and method. New York: Continuum. Gadamer, H.-G. 1989. Truth and method. New York: Continuum.
go back to reference Galatzer-Levy, I.R., and R.M. Galatzer-Levy. 2007. The revolution in psychiatric diagnosis: Problems at the foundations. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 50: 161–180.PubMedCrossRef Galatzer-Levy, I.R., and R.M. Galatzer-Levy. 2007. The revolution in psychiatric diagnosis: Problems at the foundations. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 50: 161–180.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Ghaemi, S.N. 2003. The concepts of psychiatry: A pluralistic approach to the mind and mental illness. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. Ghaemi, S.N. 2003. The concepts of psychiatry: A pluralistic approach to the mind and mental illness. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
go back to reference Ghaemi, S.N. 2009. The rise and fall of the biopsychosocial model. The British Journal of Psychiatry 195: 3–4.PubMedCrossRef Ghaemi, S.N. 2009. The rise and fall of the biopsychosocial model. The British Journal of Psychiatry 195: 3–4.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Ginter, E.J., and A. Glauser. 2001. Effective use of the DSM from a developmental/wellness perspective. In The mental health desk reference, ed. E.R. Welfel, and R.E. Ingersoll, 69–77. New York: Wiley. Ginter, E.J., and A. Glauser. 2001. Effective use of the DSM from a developmental/wellness perspective. In The mental health desk reference, ed. E.R. Welfel, and R.E. Ingersoll, 69–77. New York: Wiley.
go back to reference Grondin, J. 1994. Introduction to philosophical hermeneutics. New Haven: Yale University Press. Grondin, J. 1994. Introduction to philosophical hermeneutics. New Haven: Yale University Press.
go back to reference Healy, P. 1996. Situated rationality and hermeneutic understanding: A Gadamerian approach to rationality. International Philosophical Quarterly 36: 155–171. Healy, P. 1996. Situated rationality and hermeneutic understanding: A Gadamerian approach to rationality. International Philosophical Quarterly 36: 155–171.
go back to reference Healy, P. 2005. Rationality, hermeneutics and dialogue: Toward a viable postfoundationalist account of rationality. Aldershot: Ashgate. Healy, P. 2005. Rationality, hermeneutics and dialogue: Toward a viable postfoundationalist account of rationality. Aldershot: Ashgate.
go back to reference Jablensky, A. 1999. The nature of psychiatric classification: Issues beyond ICD-10 and DSM-IV. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry 33: 137–144.PubMedCrossRef Jablensky, A. 1999. The nature of psychiatric classification: Issues beyond ICD-10 and DSM-IV. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry 33: 137–144.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Jablensky, A. 2005. Categories, dimensions and prototypes: Critical issues for psychiatric classification. Psychopathology 38: 201–205.PubMedCrossRef Jablensky, A. 2005. Categories, dimensions and prototypes: Critical issues for psychiatric classification. Psychopathology 38: 201–205.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Kirmayer, L.J. 2005. Culture, context and experience in psychiatric diagnosis. Psychopathology 38: 192–196.PubMedCrossRef Kirmayer, L.J. 2005. Culture, context and experience in psychiatric diagnosis. Psychopathology 38: 192–196.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Lopez, S.J., L.M. Edwards, J. Teramoto Pedrotti, E.C. Prosser, S. LaRue, S. Vehige Spalitto, and J.C. Ulven. 2006. Beyond the DSM-IV: Assumptions, alternatives, and alterations. Journal of Counseling & Development 84: 259–267. Lopez, S.J., L.M. Edwards, J. Teramoto Pedrotti, E.C. Prosser, S. LaRue, S. Vehige Spalitto, and J.C. Ulven. 2006. Beyond the DSM-IV: Assumptions, alternatives, and alterations. Journal of Counseling & Development 84: 259–267.
go back to reference Martin, J., and J. Thompson. 2003. Psychotherapy as the interpretation of being: Hermeneutic perspectives on psychotherapy. Journal of Constructivist Psychology 16: 1–16.CrossRef Martin, J., and J. Thompson. 2003. Psychotherapy as the interpretation of being: Hermeneutic perspectives on psychotherapy. Journal of Constructivist Psychology 16: 1–16.CrossRef
go back to reference McLaren, N. 1998. A critical review of the biopsychosocial model. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry 32: 86–92.PubMedCrossRef McLaren, N. 1998. A critical review of the biopsychosocial model. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry 32: 86–92.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Mezzich, J.E. 2005. Positive health: Conceptual place, dimensions and implications. Psychopathology 38: 177–179.PubMedCrossRef Mezzich, J.E. 2005. Positive health: Conceptual place, dimensions and implications. Psychopathology 38: 177–179.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Mezzich, J.E., and C.E. Berganza. 2005. Purposes and models of diagnostic systems. Psychopathology 38: 162–165.PubMedCrossRef Mezzich, J.E., and C.E. Berganza. 2005. Purposes and models of diagnostic systems. Psychopathology 38: 162–165.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Mezzich, J.E., C.E. Banzato, and C.E. Berganza. 2005. Epilogue: Philosophical and methodological foundations of psychiatric diagnosis. Psychopathology 38: 228–229.PubMedCrossRef Mezzich, J.E., C.E. Banzato, and C.E. Berganza. 2005. Epilogue: Philosophical and methodological foundations of psychiatric diagnosis. Psychopathology 38: 228–229.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Moller, H.-J. 2008. Systematic of psychiatric disorders between categorical and dimensional approaches: Kraepelin’s dichotomy and beyond. European Archives of Psychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience 258: 48–73.PubMedCrossRef Moller, H.-J. 2008. Systematic of psychiatric disorders between categorical and dimensional approaches: Kraepelin’s dichotomy and beyond. European Archives of Psychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience 258: 48–73.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Mullen, P.E. 2007. A modest proposal for another phenomenological approach to psychopathology. Schizophrenia Bulletin 33: 113–121.PubMedCrossRef Mullen, P.E. 2007. A modest proposal for another phenomenological approach to psychopathology. Schizophrenia Bulletin 33: 113–121.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Muller, R.J. 2007. Doing psychiatry wrong: A critical and prescriptive look at a faltering profession. New York: Taylor and Francis. Muller, R.J. 2007. Doing psychiatry wrong: A critical and prescriptive look at a faltering profession. New York: Taylor and Francis.
go back to reference Mundt, C., and M. Backerstrass. 2005. Psychotherapy and classification: Psychological, psychodynamic, and cognitive aspects. Psychopathology 38: 219–222.PubMedCrossRef Mundt, C., and M. Backerstrass. 2005. Psychotherapy and classification: Psychological, psychodynamic, and cognitive aspects. Psychopathology 38: 219–222.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Phillips, J. 1996. Key concepts: Hermeneutics. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3: 61–69.CrossRef Phillips, J. 1996. Key concepts: Hermeneutics. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3: 61–69.CrossRef
go back to reference Phillips, J. 2004. Understanding/explanation. In The philosophy of psychiatry: A companion, ed. J. Radden, 180–190. New York: Oxford University Press. Phillips, J. 2004. Understanding/explanation. In The philosophy of psychiatry: A companion, ed. J. Radden, 180–190. New York: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Phillips, J. 2005. Idiographic formulations, symbols, narratives, context and meaning. Psychopathology 38: 180–184.PubMedCrossRef Phillips, J. 2005. Idiographic formulations, symbols, narratives, context and meaning. Psychopathology 38: 180–184.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Pilgrim, D. 2002. The biopsychosocial model in Anglo-American psychiatry: Past, present and future? Journal of Mental Health 11: 585–594.CrossRef Pilgrim, D. 2002. The biopsychosocial model in Anglo-American psychiatry: Past, present and future? Journal of Mental Health 11: 585–594.CrossRef
go back to reference Polkinghorne, D.E. 2000. Psychological inquiry and the pragmatic and hermeneutic traditions. Theory & Psychology 10: 453–479.CrossRef Polkinghorne, D.E. 2000. Psychological inquiry and the pragmatic and hermeneutic traditions. Theory & Psychology 10: 453–479.CrossRef
go back to reference Polkinghorne, D.E. 2004. Practice and the human sciences: The case for a judgement-based practice of care. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press. Polkinghorne, D.E. 2004. Practice and the human sciences: The case for a judgement-based practice of care. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
go back to reference Ryder, M. 2005. Scientism. In Encyclopedia of science, technology, ethics, ed. C. Mitcham, 1735–1736. Detroit: Macmillan Reference. Ryder, M. 2005. Scientism. In Encyclopedia of science, technology, ethics, ed. C. Mitcham, 1735–1736. Detroit: Macmillan Reference.
go back to reference Sadler, J.Z. 2005. Values and psychiatric diagnosis. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Sadler, J.Z. 2005. Values and psychiatric diagnosis. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Sarbin, T.R. 1997. On the futility of psychiatric diagnostic manuals (DSMs) and the return of personal agency. Applied and Preventive Psychology 6: 233–243.CrossRef Sarbin, T.R. 1997. On the futility of psychiatric diagnostic manuals (DSMs) and the return of personal agency. Applied and Preventive Psychology 6: 233–243.CrossRef
go back to reference Shorter, E. 1997. A history of psychiatry: From the era of the asylum to the age of prozac. Oxford, UK: Wiley. Shorter, E. 1997. A history of psychiatry: From the era of the asylum to the age of prozac. Oxford, UK: Wiley.
go back to reference Strauss, J.S. 2005. Diagnosis and reality: A noun is a terrible thing to waste. Psychopathology 38: 189–191.PubMedCrossRef Strauss, J.S. 2005. Diagnosis and reality: A noun is a terrible thing to waste. Psychopathology 38: 189–191.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Thornton, T. 2008. Should comprehensive diagnosis include idiographic understanding? Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 11: 293–302.CrossRef Thornton, T. 2008. Should comprehensive diagnosis include idiographic understanding? Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 11: 293–302.CrossRef
go back to reference Todres, L. 2008. Being with that: The relevance of embodied understanding for practice. Qualitative Health Research 18: 1566–1573.PubMedCrossRef Todres, L. 2008. Being with that: The relevance of embodied understanding for practice. Qualitative Health Research 18: 1566–1573.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference van Praag, H.M. 2008. Kraepelin, biological psychiatry, and beyond. European Archives of Psychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience 258: 29–32.PubMedCrossRef van Praag, H.M. 2008. Kraepelin, biological psychiatry, and beyond. European Archives of Psychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience 258: 29–32.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Widdershoven, G.A. 2000. The doctor-patient relationship as a Gadamerian dialogue: A response to Arnason. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy: A European Journal 3: 25–27.CrossRef Widdershoven, G.A. 2000. The doctor-patient relationship as a Gadamerian dialogue: A response to Arnason. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy: A European Journal 3: 25–27.CrossRef
go back to reference Williams, R.N. 1990. The metaphysic of things and discourse about them. In Reconsidering psychology, ed. J.E. Faulconer, and R.N. Williams, 136–150. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press. Williams, R.N. 1990. The metaphysic of things and discourse about them. In Reconsidering psychology, ed. J.E. Faulconer, and R.N. Williams, 136–150. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
go back to reference Yanchar, S.C., and J.R. Hill. 2003. What is psychology about? Toward an explicit ontology. Journal of Humanistic Psychology 43: 11–32.CrossRef Yanchar, S.C., and J.R. Hill. 2003. What is psychology about? Toward an explicit ontology. Journal of Humanistic Psychology 43: 11–32.CrossRef
Metadata
Title
DSM diagnosis and beyond: on the need for a hermeneutically-informed biopsychosocial framework
Author
Paul Healy
Publication date
01-05-2011
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy / Issue 2/2011
Print ISSN: 1386-7423
Electronic ISSN: 1572-8633
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-010-9284-x

Other articles of this Issue 2/2011

Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2/2011 Go to the issue

Short Literature Notices

Short literature notices