Skip to main content
Log in

The consciousness continuum: from “qualia” to “free will”

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Psychological Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The consciousness continuum is seen as extending from simple sensory experiences to complex subjective constructions resulting in the apparent exercise of conscious will. The phenomena between these two extremes include spontaneously occurring mental contents, unintended perceptual experiences, memory retrievals, and problem solving including feedback of conscious contents. Two factors describe this continuum: The presence or absence of intention (psychologically defined) and the complexity of the cognitive construction involved. Among other benefits, such an analysis is intended to provide an alternative to metaphysical and vague concepts such as qualia, free will, and intentionality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is not the place, nor does space permit, to discuss the relationship between these constructions and the variety of other distinctions available in the literature.

  2. I will not deal with the possibility that intentions may sometimes be coextensive with the intended act.

  3. See also Kahneman and Treisman (1984).

  4. See also Pashler (1998)

  5. For more extensive descriptions of these studies, see Mandler (1994).

  6. For a review of relevant studies, see Kvavilashvili & Mandler (2004).

  7. See Mandler (1980) for a discussion of the processes involved.

  8. Amnesic patients show unimpaired performance on implicit memory of previous primed words, etc. (e.g., Warrington & Weiskrantz, 1971; Graf, Squire, & Mandler, 1984). These patients are presumably accessing the material “unintentionally.”

  9. Related to these more complex phenomena are the extensive demonstrations by Bargh, Gollwitzer, Lee-Chai, Barndollar, & Troetschel how unconscious (automated, uncontrolled) processes guide and control overt and conscious action, e.g., Bargh, et al. (2001) and Uleman & Bargh(1989).

  10. The fact that conscious experience can affect subsequent action and experience should provide serious pause for defenders of an epiphenomenal position that speaks of an ineffective consciousness.

  11. However, we have known for some time that spurious mental ascriptions such as false recall and recognition memories may be easily produced experimentally. By themselves they do not provide definitive proof of the mechanism(s) underlying the original phenomenon.

  12. Granted that we do not know how conscious thought might cause some action, we are no wiser as to the processes whereby unconscious mechanisms do so.

  13. The reader is directed to the original chapter for more elaborations of this and other aspects of apparent exercises of “free will.” I note that when we advocated a belief in free will as making more choices and alternatives possible, we were accused by some of our audience of being hypocritical by advocating something we did not believe in.

  14. I thank Michael Mandler for suggesting this argument.

  15. Anderson (1984), Johnson & Raye (1981).

References

  • Anderson, R..E. (1984). Did I do it or did I imagine doing it? Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 113, 594–613.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. A., Gollwitzer, P. M., Lee-Chai, A., Barndollar, K., & Troetschel, R. (2001). The automated will: Nonconscious activation and pursuit of behavioral goals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81, 1014–1027.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bekerian, D. A. (1992). Autobiographical remembering: An integrative approach. In M. A. Conway, D. C. Rubin, H. Spinler, & W. A. Wagenaar, (Eds.), Theoretical perspectives on autobiographical memory. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berntsen, D. (1996). Involuntary autobiographical memories. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 10, 455–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berntsen, D. (1998). Voluntary and involuntary access to autobiographical memory. Memory, 6, 113–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brenner, C. (1976). Psychoanalytic technique and psychic conflict. New York: International Universities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewin, C. R. (1998). Intrusive autobiographical memories in depression and post-traumatic stress disorder. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 12, 359–370.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bühler, K. (1907). Tatsachen und Probleme zu einer Psychologie der Denkvorgänge. Archiv für die Gesamte Psychologie, 9, 297–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chapman, C. R. (1996). Limbic processes and the affective dimension of pain. In G. Carli, & M. Zimmermann, (Eds.), Towards the neurobiology of chronic pain (pp. 63–81). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conway, M. A., & Pleydell-Pearce, C. W. (2000). The construction of autobiographical memories in the self-memory system. Psychological Review, 107, 261–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coslett, H. B., & Saffran E. M. (1989). Evidence for preserved reading in ‘pure alexia’. Brain, 112, 327–359.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coslett, H. B., Saffran, E. M., Greenbaum, S., & Schwartz, H. (1993). Reading in pure alexia: The effect of strategy. Brain, 116, 21–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C., & Haugeland, J. (1987). Intentionality. In R. L. Gregory, (Ed.), The Oxford companion to the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dixon, N. F. (1971). Subliminal perception: The nature of a controversy. London: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dulany, D. E. (1991). Conscious representation and thought systems. In R. S. Wyer, & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Advances in social cognition. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, C., & Paul, I. H. (1959). The effect of subliminal visual stimulation on imagery and dreams: A validation study. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, 7, 35–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiss, H., Goldberg, F., & Klein, G. S. (1963). Effects of subliminal stimulation on imagery and discrimination. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 17, 31–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1982). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. In G. Watson, (Ed.), Free will (pp. 81–95). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graf, P., & Mandler, G. (1984). Activation makes words more accessible, but not necessarily more retrievable. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 23, 553–568.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graf, P., Squire, L. R., & Mandler G. (1984). The information that amnesic patients do not forget. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 10, 164–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. K., & Raye, C. L. (1981). Reality monitoring. Psychological Review, 88, 67–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Treisman, A. (1984). Changing views of attention and automaticity. In R. Parasuraman, & D. R. Davies, (Eds.), Varieties of attention (pp. 29–61). New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A., & Feuerstein, N. (1976). The recovery of incidentally acquired information. Acta Psychologica, 40, 463–474.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvavilashvili, L., & Mandler, G. (2004). Out of your mind: A study of involuntary semantic memories. Cognitive Psychology, 48, 47–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandler, G. (1975). Consciousness: Respectable, useful, and probably necessary. In R. Solso, (Ed.), Information processing and cognition: The Loyola symposium (pp. 229–254). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandler, G. (1980). Recognizing: The judgment of previous occurrence. Psychological Review, 87, 252–271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandler, G. (1986). Reminding, recalling, recognizing: Different memories? In F. Klix, & H. Hagendorf (Eds.), Human memory and cognitive capabilities. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandler, G. (1994). Hypermnesia, incubation, and mind-popping: On remembering without really trying. In C. Umiltà, & M. Moscovitch, (Eds.), Attention and performance XV: Conscious and nonconscious information processing (pp. 3–33). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandler, G. (1996). Consciousness redux. In J. C. Cohen, J. W. Schooler, (Eds.), Scientific approaches to consciousness: The Twenty-fifth Carnegie Symposium on Cognition (pp. 479–498). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandler, G. (2002). Consciousness recovered: Psychological functions and origins of conscious thought. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandler, G. (in press). Free will for everyone—with flaws. Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

  • Mandler, G., & Kessen, W. (1974). The appearance of free will. In S. C.Brown, (Ed.), Philosophy of psychology (pp. 305–324). London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcel, A. J. (1983). Conscious and unconscious perception: Experiments on visual masking and word recognition. Cognitive Psychology, 15, 197–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michelon, P., & Zacks, J. M. (2003). What is primed in priming from imagery? Psychological Research, 67, 71–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nakamura, Y. (1989). Explorations in implicit perceptual processing: Studies of preconscious information processing. Unpublished doctoral thesis, University of California, San Diego, La Jolla, CA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, J. I. (1974). Motion sensitivity in peripheral vision. Perception, 3, 151–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Overson, C., & Mandler, G. (1987). Indirect word priming in connected semantic and phonological contexts. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 25, 229–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pashler, H. E. (1998). The psychology of attention. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pilotti, M., Gallo, D. A., & Roediger, H. L. I. (2000). Effects of hearing words, imagining hearing words, and reading on auditory implicit and explicit memory tests. Memory and Cognition, 28, 1406–1418.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pine, F. (1964). The bearing of psychoanalytic theory on selected issues in research on marginal stimuli. Journal of Nervous and Mental Diseases, 138, 68–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, P., McGinnis, D., & Bladt, L. (1994). The unexpected excursion: Passive memories in everyday life. Paper presented at a Conference on Practical Aspects of Memory. University of Maryland, College Park, MD.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schooler, J. W., Ohlsson, S., & Brooks, K. (1993). Thoughts beyond words: When language overshadows insight. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 122, 166–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siewert, C. (2002). Consciousness and intentionality. In E. Zalta, (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spence, D. P. (1988). Passive remembering. In U. Neisser, & E. Winograd, (Eds.), Remembering reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stuart, G. P., & Jones, D. M. (1996). From auditory image to auditory percept: Facilitation through common processes? Memory and Cognition, 24, 296–304.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, A. K., & Loftus, E. F. (2002). Creating bizarre false memories through imagination. Memory and Cognition, 30, 423–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2003). Qualia. In E. N. Zalta, (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2003 edition): URL=<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2003/entries/qualia/>.

  • Uleman, J. S., & Bargh, J. A. (1989). Unintended thought. New York: Guilford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallas, G. (1926). The art of thought. New York: Harcourt Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warrington, E. K., & Weiskrantz, L. (1970). Amnesia: Consolidation or retrieval? Nature, 228, 628–630.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M. (2003). The mind’s best trick: How we experience conscious will. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 65–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M., & Wheatley, T. (1999). Apparent mental causation: Sources of the experience of will. American Psychologist, 54, 480–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiskrantz, L. (1986). Blindsight: A case study and implications. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werner, H. (1956). Microgenesis and aphasia. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 52, 347–353.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westcott, M. R. (1977). Free will: An exercise in metaphysical truth or psychological consequences. Canadian Psychological Review, 18, 249–263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winograd, E. (1993). Memory in the laboratory and everyday memory: The case for both. In J. M. Puckett, & H. W. Reese, (Eds.), Mechanisms of everyday cognition. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wippich, W., Mecklenbräuker, S., & Halfter, M. (1989). Implicit memory in spelling from word images. Psychological Research, 51, 208–216.3

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am indebted to Tony Marcel for instructive discussions of several of the issues involved here, and to Lia Kvavilashvili for helpful comments on an earlier version.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to George Mandler.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mandler, G. The consciousness continuum: from “qualia” to “free will”. Psychological Research 69, 330–337 (2005). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00426-004-0206-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00426-004-0206-5

Keywords

Navigation